Psychology Wiki
(Created page with "{{PhilPsy}} {{Infobox philosopher | region = Western Philosophy | era = Ancient philosophy | color = #B0C4DE | image = Petrarca-M...")
 
No edit summary
 
Line 15: Line 15:
 
}}
 
}}
   
'''Pyrrho''' ({{lang-el|Πύρρων}}, ''gen''.: Πύρρωνος; ca. 360 BC – ca. 270 BC), a Greek [[philosopher]] of [[classical antiquity]], is credited as being the first [[Skeptic]] philosopher, and the inspiration for the school known as '''[[Pyrrhonism]]''' founded by [[Aenesidemus]] in the 1st century BC.
+
'''Pyrrho''' ({{lang-el|Πύρρων}}, ''gen''.: Πύρρωνος; ca. 360 BC – ca. 270 BC), a Greek [[philosopher]] of classical antiquity, is credited as being the first [[Skeptic]] philosopher, and the inspiration for the school known as '''[[Pyrrhonism]]''' founded by [[Aenesidemus]] in the 1st century BC.
   
 
== Life ==
 
== Life ==
Pyrrho was from [[Elis]], on the [[Ionian Sea]]. [[Diogenes Laertius]], quoting from [[Apollodorus]], says that Pyrrho was at first a painter, and that pictures by him were exhibited in the gymnasium at Elis. Later he was diverted to philosophy by the works of [[Democritus]], and according to Diogenes Laertius became acquainted with the [[Megarian school of philosophy|Megarian dialectic]] through [[Bryson of Achaea|Bryson]], pupil of [[Stilpo]].<ref>Diogenes' testimony is doubtful. See Bett (2000) 1.</ref>
+
Pyrrho was from Elis, on the Ionian Sea. [[Diogenes Laertius]], quoting from [[Apollodorus]], says that Pyrrho was at first a painter, and that pictures by him were exhibited in the gymnasium at Elis. Later he was diverted to philosophy by the works of [[Democritus]], and according to Diogenes Laertius became acquainted with the [[Megarian school of philosophy|Megarian dialectic]] through [[Bryson of Achaea|Bryson]], pupil of [[Stilpo]].<ref>Diogenes' testimony is doubtful. See Bett (2000) 1.</ref>
   
Pyrrho, along with [[Anaxarchus]], travelled with [[Alexander the Great]] on his exploration of the East, and studied under the [[Gymnosophists]] in [[India]] and the [[Magi]] in [[Achaemenid Empire|Persia]]. This exposure to [[Eastern philosophy]] seems to have inspired him to adopt a life of solitude; returning to Elis, he lived in poor circumstances, but was highly honored by the Elians and also by the Athenians, who conferred upon him the rights of citizenship.
+
Pyrrho, along with [[Anaxarchus]], travelled with Alexander the Great on his exploration of the East, and studied under the [[Gymnosophists]] in India and the [[Magi]] in [[Achaemenid Empire|Persia]]. This exposure to [[Eastern philosophy]] seems to have inspired him to adopt a life of solitude; returning to Elis, he lived in poor circumstances, but was highly honored by the Elians and also by the Athenians, who conferred upon him the rights of citizenship.
   
 
Pyrrho wrote nothing. His doctrines were recorded in the satiric writings of his pupil [[Timon of Phlius]] (the Sillographer). Unfortunately these works are mostly lost. Today Pyrrho's ideas are known mainly through the book ''Outlines of Pyrrhonism'' written by the Greek physician [[Sextus Empiricus]].
 
Pyrrho wrote nothing. His doctrines were recorded in the satiric writings of his pupil [[Timon of Phlius]] (the Sillographer). Unfortunately these works are mostly lost. Today Pyrrho's ideas are known mainly through the book ''Outlines of Pyrrhonism'' written by the Greek physician [[Sextus Empiricus]].

Latest revision as of 20:18, 10 September 2011

Assessment | Biopsychology | Comparative | Cognitive | Developmental | Language | Individual differences | Personality | Philosophy | Social |
Methods | Statistics | Clinical | Educational | Industrial | Professional items | World psychology |

Philosophy Index: Aesthetics · Epistemology · Ethics · Logic · Metaphysics · Consciousness · Philosophy of Language · Philosophy of Mind · Philosophy of Science · Social and Political philosophy · Philosophies · Philosophers · List of lists


Pyrrho
File:Petrarca-Meister 001.jpg
Full name Pyrrho
Born ca. 360 BC
Elis, Greece
Died ca. 270 BC
Era Ancient philosophy
Region Western Philosophy
School Skepticism

Pyrrho (Greek: Πύρρων

, gen.: Πύρρωνος; ca. 360 BC – ca. 270 BC), a Greek philosopher of classical antiquity, is credited as being the first Skeptic philosopher, and the inspiration for the school known as Pyrrhonism founded by Aenesidemus in the 1st century BC.

Life

Pyrrho was from Elis, on the Ionian Sea. Diogenes Laertius, quoting from Apollodorus, says that Pyrrho was at first a painter, and that pictures by him were exhibited in the gymnasium at Elis. Later he was diverted to philosophy by the works of Democritus, and according to Diogenes Laertius became acquainted with the Megarian dialectic through Bryson, pupil of Stilpo.[1]

Pyrrho, along with Anaxarchus, travelled with Alexander the Great on his exploration of the East, and studied under the Gymnosophists in India and the Magi in Persia. This exposure to Eastern philosophy seems to have inspired him to adopt a life of solitude; returning to Elis, he lived in poor circumstances, but was highly honored by the Elians and also by the Athenians, who conferred upon him the rights of citizenship.

Pyrrho wrote nothing. His doctrines were recorded in the satiric writings of his pupil Timon of Phlius (the Sillographer). Unfortunately these works are mostly lost. Today Pyrrho's ideas are known mainly through the book Outlines of Pyrrhonism written by the Greek physician Sextus Empiricus.

Philosophy

The main principle of Pyrrho's thought is expressed by the word acatalepsia, which connotes the ability to withhold assent from doctrines regarding the truth of things in their own nature; against every statement its contradiction may be advanced with equal justification. Secondly, it is necessary in view of this fact to preserve an attitude of intellectual suspense, or, as Timon expressed it, no assertion can be known to be better than another. Thirdly, Pyrrho applied these results to life in general, concluding that, since nothing can be known, the only proper attitude is ataraxia, "freedom from worry". ("By suspending judgment, by confining oneself to phenomena or objects as they appear, and by asserting nothing definite as to how they really are, one can escape the perplexities of life and attain an imperturbable peace of mind.")

The proper course of the sage, said Pyrrho, is to ask himself three questions. Firstly we must ask what things are and how they are constituted. Secondly, we ask how we are related to these things. Thirdly, we ask what ought to be our attitude towards them. Pyrrho's answer was that things are indistinguishable, unmeasurable, undecidable, and no more this than that, or both this and that and neither this nor that. He concluded that human senses neither transmit truths nor lie.[2] Humanity cannot know the inner substance of things, only how things appear.

The impossibility of knowledge, even in regard to our own ignorance or doubt, should induce the wise man to withdraw into himself, avoiding the stress and emotion which belong to the contest of vain imaginings. This theory of the impossibility of knowledge is the first and the most thorough exposition of noncognitivism in the history of thought.[citation needed] Its ethical implications may be compared with the ideal tranquility of the Stoics and the Epicureans.

See also

  • Callisthenes

Notes

  1. Diogenes' testimony is doubtful. See Bett (2000) 1.
  2. Long and Sedley (1987) vol. 1, pp. 14-17, vol. 2, pp. 5-7.

References

  • This article incorporates text from the Encyclopædia Britannica, Eleventh Edition, a publication now in the public domain.
  • Algra, K., Barnes, J., Mansfeld, J. and Schofield, M. (eds.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).
  • Annas, Julia and Barnes, Jonathan, The Modes of Scepticism: Ancient Texts and Modern Interpretations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).
  • Bett, Richard, "Aristocles on Timon on Pyrrho: The Text, Its Logic and its Credibility" Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12 (1994a): 137-181.
  • Bett, Richard, "What did Pyrrho Think about the Nature of the Divine and the Good?" Phronesis 39 (1994b): 303-337.
  • Bett, Richard, Pyrrho, his antecedents, and his legacy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
  • Brunschwig, Jacques, "Introduction: the beginnings of Hellenistic epistemology" in Algra, Barnes, Mansfeld and Schofield (eds.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999): 229-259.
  • Burnyeat, Myles (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983).
  • Burnyeat, Myles and Frede, Michael (eds.), The Original Sceptics: A Controversy (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1997).
  • Doomen, Jasper, "The Problems of Scepticism" Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 10 (2007): 36-52.
  • Hankinson, R.J., The Sceptics (London: Routledge, 1995).
  • Long, A.A., Hellenistic Philosophy: Stoics, Epicureans, Sceptics (University of California Press, 1986).
  • Long, A.A. and Sedley, David, The Hellenistic Philosophers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987).
  • Striker, Gisela, "On the difference between the Pyrrhonists and the Academics" in G. Striker, Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996): 135-149.
  • Striker, Gisela, "Sceptical strategies" in G. Striker, Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996): 92-115.
  • Striker, Gisela, "The Ten Tropes of Aenesidemus" in G. Striker, Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996): 116-134.
  • Svavarsson, Svavar Hrafn, "Pyrrho’s dogmatic nature", The Classical Quarterly 52 (2002): 248-56.
  • Svavarsson, Svavar Hrafn, "Pyrrho’s undecidable nature", Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 27 (2004): 249-295.

External links

Template:Ancient Greek skepticism

This page uses Creative Commons Licensed content from Wikipedia (view authors).