Psychology Wiki
No edit summary
 
No edit summary
Tag: rollback
(5 intermediate revisions by 4 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{PhiPsy}}
+
{{PhilPsy}}
  +
{{PsyPerspective}}
  +
'''Plato''' (Greek: ''{{polytonic|Πλάτων}}'', ''Plátōn'', "broad")<ref>[[Diogenes Laertius]] 3.4; p. 21, David Sedley, [http://assets.cambridge.org/052158/4922/sample/0521584922ws.pdf ''Plato's Cratylus''], Cambridge University Press 2003</ref> (428/427 BC{{Ref_label|A|a|none}} – 348/347 BC), was a [[Classical Greece|Classical]] Greek [[philosopher]], [[mathematician]], writer of philosophical dialogues, and founder of the Platonic Academy in Athens, the first institution of higher learning in the western world. Along with his mentor, [[Socrates]], and his student, [[Aristotle]], Plato helped to lay the foundations of [[Western philosophy]].<ref name="Br">{{cite encyclopedia|title=Plato|encyclopedia=Encyclopaedia Britannica|year=2002}}</ref> Plato was originally a student of Socrates, and was as much influenced by his thinking as by what he saw as his teacher's unjust death.
   
  +
Plato's sophistication as a writer is evident in his [[Socratic dialogues]]; thirty-five dialogues and thirteen letters have traditionally been ascribed to him, although modern scholarship doubts the authenticity of at least some of these.<ref>For example, some were excluded from Thrasyllus' tetralogies. See ''e.g.'' the table of contents to John M. Cooper (ed.), ''Plato: Complete Works'', Hackett, 1997.</ref> Plato's writings have been published in several fashions; this has led to several conventions regarding the naming and referencing of Plato's texts.
[[Image:Delphi Platon statue 1.jpg|thumb|200px|Plato]]
 
'''Plato''' ([[Greek language|Greek]]: Πλάτων, ''Plátōn'') (c.[[427 BC|427]]&ndash;c.[[347 BC]]) was an immensely influential [[Ancient Greece|ancient Greek]] [[philosopher]], a student of [[Socrates]], writer of philosophical dialogues, and founder of the [[Academy]] in [[Athens]] where [[Aristotle]] studied.
 
   
  +
Although there is little question that Plato lectured at the Academy that he founded, the [[Pedagogy|pedagogical]] function of his dialogues, if any, is not known with certainty. The dialogues since Plato's time have been used to teach a range of subjects, mostly including [[philosophy]], [[logic]], [[rhetoric]], [[mathematics]], and other subjects about which he wrote.
Plato lectured extensively at the Academy, and wrote on many philosophical issues. The most important writings of Plato are his [[dialogue]]s, although a handful of [[epigram]]s also survived, and some [[letter]]s have come down to us under his name. It is believed that all of Plato's authentic dialogues survive. However, some dialogues ascribed to Plato by the Greeks are now considered by the consensus of scholars to be either suspect (e.g., ''[[Alcibiades (dialogues)|First Alcibiades]]'', ''[[Clitophon (dialogue)|Clitophon]]'') or probably spurious (such as ''[[Demodocus (dialogue)|Demodocus]]'', or the ''[[Alcibiades (dialogues)|Second Alcibiades]]''). The letters are all considered as probably spurious, with the possible exception of the Seventh Letter.
 
 
[[Socrates]] is often a character in the dialogues of Plato. How much of the content and argument of any given dialogue is Socrates' point of view, and how much of it is Plato's, is heavily disputed, since Socrates himself did not write down his teachings; this is often known as the "[[Socratic problem]]". However, Plato was doubtless strongly influenced by Socrates' teachings, so many of the ideas presented, at least in his early works, were probably borrowings.
 
   
 
==Biography==
 
==Biography==
  +
===Early life===
Plato was born in Athens or [[Aegina]] in May or December in [[428 BC|428]] or [[427 BC]]. He was raised in a moderately well-to-do aristocratic family. His father was named Ariston, and his mother Perictione. His family claimed descent from the ancient [[King of Athens|Athenian kings]], and he was related &mdash; though there is disagreement as to exactly how &mdash; to the prominent politician [[Critias]]. According to a late [[Hellenistic]] account by [[Diogenes Laertius]], Plato's given name was ''Aristocles'', whereas his wrestling coach, Ariston of Argos, dubbed him ''Platon'', meaning ''broad'' on account of his robust figure. Diogenes mentions alternative accounts that Plato derived his name from the breadth (''platutês'') of his eloquence, or else because he was very wide (''platus'') across the forehead. According to [[Dicaearchus]], Plato wrestled at the [[Isthmian games]]. Such was his learning and ability that the ancient Greeks declared him to be the son of Apollo and told how, in his infancy, bees had settled on his lips, as prophecy of the honeyed words which were to flow from them.
 
  +
{{Main |Early life of Plato}}
  +
====Birth and family====
  +
Based on ancient sources, most modern scholars estimate that he was born in Athens or [[Aegina]]{{Ref_label|B|b|none}} between 429 and 423 BC{{Ref_label|A|a|none}} His father was [[Ariston (Athenian)|Ariston]]. According to a disputed tradition, reported by [[Diogenes Laertius]], Ariston traced his descent from the [[king of Athens]], [[Codrus]], and the king of [[Messenia]], [[Melanthus]].<ref name="DW">Diogenes Laertius, ''Life of Plato'', III<br>* D. Nails, "Ariston", 53<br>* U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, ''Plato'', 46</ref> Plato's mother was [[Perictione]], whose family boasted of a relationship with the famous Athenian [[legislator|lawmaker]] and [[lyric poetry|lyric poet]] [[Solon]].<ref name="LaI">Diogenes Laertius, ''Life of Plato'', I</ref> Perictione was sister of [[Charmides]] and niece of [[Critias]], both prominent figures of the [[Thirty Tyrants]], the brief [[oligarchy|oligarchic]] [[regime]], which followed on the collapse of Athens at the end of the [[Peloponnesian War]] (404-403 BC).<ref name="TW1">W. K. C. Guthrie, ''A History of Greek Philosophy''', IV, 10<br>* A.E. Taylor, ''Plato'', xiv<br>* U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, ''Plato'', 47</ref> Besides Plato himself, Ariston and Perictione had three other children; these were two sons, [[Adeimantus]] and [[Glaucon]], and a daughter [[Potone]], the mother of [[Speusippus]] (the nephew and successor of Plato as head of his philosophical Academy).<ref name="TW1" /> According to the ''[[Republic (Plato)|Republic]]'', Adeimantus and Glaucon were older than Plato.<ref name="PlRep368a">Plato, ''Republic'', 2.[http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0168;query=section%3D%23191;layout=;loc=2.368b 368a]<br>* U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, ''Plato'', 47</ref> Nevertheless, in his [[Memorabilia (Xenophon)|Memorabilia]], [[Xenophon]] presents Glaucon as younger than Plato.<ref>Xenophon, ''Memorabilia'', 3.6.[http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0208&layout=&loc=3.6.1 1]</ref>
   
  +
Ariston tried to force his attentions on Perictione, but failed of his purpose; then the [[Twelve Olympians|ancient Greek god]] [[Apollo]] appeared to him in a vision, and, as a result of it, Ariston left Perictione unmolested.<ref name="Ap1">Apuleius, ''De Dogmate Platonis'', 1<br>* Diogenes Laertius, ''Life of Plato'', I<br>{{cite encyclopedia|title=Plato|encyclopedia=Suda}}</ref> Another legend related that, while he was sleeping as an infant, bees had settled on the lips of Plato; an augury of the sweetness of style in which he would discourse philosophy.<ref>Cicero, ''De Divinatione'', I, 36</ref>
Plato became a pupil of Socrates in his youth, and&mdash;at least according to his own account&mdash;he attended his master's trial, though not his execution. He was deeply affected by the city's treatment of Socrates, and much of his early work records his memories of his teacher. It is suggested that much of his [[ethics|ethical]] writing is in pursuit of a society where similar injustices could not occur. During the twelve years following the death of Socrates, he traveled extensively in Italy, Sicily, Egypt, and Cyrene in a quest for knowledge.
 
   
  +
Ariston appears to have died in Plato's childhood, although the precise dating of his death is difficult.<ref name="TN">D. Nails, "Ariston", 53<br>* A.E. Taylor, ''Plato'', xiv</ref> Perictione then married [[Pyrilampes]], her mother's brother,<ref name="NA229">Plato, ''Charmides'', [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0176&query=section%3D%23376&layout=&loc=Charm.%20157e 158a]<br>* D. Nails, "Perictione", 53</ref> who had served many times as an ambassador to the [[Persian Empire|Persian court]] and was a friend of [[Pericles]], the leader of the democratic faction in Athens.<ref name="P13">Plato, ''Charmides'', [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0176&query=section%3D%23376&layout=&loc=Charm.%20157e 158a]<br>* Plutarch, ''Pericles'', [[s:Lives/Pericles#13|IV]]</ref> Pyrilampes had a son from a previous marriage, Demus, who was famous for his beauty.<ref>Plato, ''Gorgias'', [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0178;query=section%3D%23620;layout=;loc=Gorg.%20481c 481d] and [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0178;query=section%3D%23778;layout=;loc=Gorg.%20513chttp://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0178;query=section%3D%23620;layout=;loc=Gorg.%20481c 513b]<br>* Aristophanes, ''Wasps'', [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0044;query=card%3D%233;layout=;loc=54 97]</ref> Perictione gave birth to Pyrilampes' second son, Antiphon, the half-brother of Plato, who appears in ''[[Parmenides (Plato)|Parmenides]]''.<ref name="P126c">Plato, ''Parmenides'', [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0174;query=section%3D%233;layout=;loc=Parm.%20126b 126c]</ref>
After his return to Athens at the age of 40, Plato founded one of the earliest known organized schools in Western civilization on a plot of land in the Grove of Academe. The [[Academy]] was "a large enclosure of ground which was once the property of a citizen at Athens named [[Academus]]... some, however, say that it received its name from an ancient hero" (Robinson, Arch. Graec. I i 16), and it operated until AD [[529]], when it was closed by [[Justinian I]] of [[Byzantium]], who saw it as a threat to the propagation of [[Christianity]]. Many intellectuals were schooled in the Academy, the most prominent one being [[Aristotle]].
 
   
  +
In contrast to his reticence about himself, Plato used to introduce his distinguished relatives into his dialogues, or to mention them with some precision: Charmides has one named after him; Critias speaks in both ''[[Charmides (dialogue)|Charmides]]'' and ''[[Protagoras (dialogue)|Protagoras]]''; Adeimantus and Glaucon take prominent parts in the ''[[Republic (Plato)|Republic]]''.<ref name="G11">W. K. C. Guthrie, ''A History of Greek Philosophy'', IV, 11</ref> From these and other references one can reconstruct his [[family tree]], and this suggests a considerable amount of family pride. According to Burnet, "the opening scene of the ''Charmides'' is a glorification of the whole [family] connection ... Plato's dialogues are not only a memorial to Socrates, but also the happier days of his own family".<ref name="Kahn186">C.H. Kahn, ''Plato and the Socratic Dialogue'', 186</ref>
Plato was also deeply influenced by a number of prior philosophers, including: the [[Pythagoreans]], whose notions of numerical [[harmony]] have clear echoes in Plato's notion of [[the Forms]]; [[Anaxagoras]], who taught Socrates and who held that the [[mind]], or [[reason]], pervades everything; and [[Parmenides]], who argued for the unity of all things and may have influenced Plato's concept of the [[soul]].
 
   
==Work==
+
====Name====
  +
According to [[Diogenes Laërtius]], the philosopher was named ''Aristocles'' after his grandfather, but his [[wrestling]] coach, Ariston of Argos, dubbed him "Platon", meaning "broad," on account of his robust figure.<ref name="LaIV">Diogenes Laertius, ''Life of Plato'', IV</ref> According to the sources mentioned by Diogenes (all dating from the [[Alexandrian period]]), Plato derived his name from the breadth (''platytês'') of his eloquence, or else because he was very wide (''platýs'') across the forehead.<ref name="LaN">Diogenes Laertius, ''Life of Plato'', IV<br>* A. Notopoulos, ''The Name of Plato'', 135</ref> In the 21st century some scholars disputed Diogenes, and argued that the legend about his name being ''Aristocles'' originated in the [[Hellenistic civilization|Hellenistic age]].{{Ref_label|C|c|none}}'''
[[Image:Plato-raphael.jpg|thumb|left|280px|[[Raphael]]'s Plato in ''The School of Athens'' fresco, probably in the likeness of [[Leonardo da Vinci]]. Plato gestures to the heavens, representing his belief in [[The Forms]].]]
 
   
===Themes===
+
====Education====
  +
[[Apuleius]] informs us that Speusippus praised Plato's quickness of mind and modesty as a boy, and the "first fruits of his youth infused with hard work and love of study".<ref name="Ap2">Apuleius, ''De Dogmate Platonis'', 2</ref> Plato must have been instructed in grammar, music, and [[gymnastics]] by the most distinguished teachers of his time.<ref name="DS">Diogenes Laertius, ''Life of Plato'', IV<br>* W. Smith, ''Plato'', 393</ref> [[Dicaearchus]] went so far as to say that Plato wrestled at the [[Isthmian games]].<ref name="LaV">Diogenes Laertius, ''Life of Plato'', V</ref> Plato had also attended courses of philosophy; before meeting Socrates, he first became acquainted with [[Cratylus]] (a disciple of [[Heraclitus]], a prominent [[Pre-Socratic philosophy|pre-Socratic]] Greek philosopher) and the Heraclitean doctrines.<ref name="Ar987a">Aristotle, ''Metaphysics'', 1.[http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0052&query=section%3D%2315&layout=&loc=1.987b 987a]</ref>
Unlike Socrates, Plato wrote down his philosophical views, leaving behind a considerable number of manuscripts.
 
   
  +
===Later life===
In Plato's writings are debates concerning the best possible form of [[government]], featuring adherents of [[aristocracy]], [[democracy]], [[monarchy]] as well as other issues. A central theme is the conflict between [[nature]] and [[convention]], concerning the role of [[heredity]] and the [[environmental psychology|environment]] on human [[intelligence (trait)|intelligence]] and [[personality]] long before the modern "[[nature versus nurture]]" debate began in the time of [[Thomas Hobbes]] and [[John Locke]], with its modern continuation in such controversial works as ''[[The Mismeasure of Man]]'' and ''[[The Bell Curve]]''.
 
  +
Plato may have traveled in [[Italy]], [[Sicily]], [[Egypt]] and [[Cyrene, Libya|Cyrene]].<ref>{{cite journal
  +
|last = McEvoy
  +
|first = James
  +
|year = 1984
  +
|title = Plato and The Wisdom of Egypt
  +
|journal = Irish Philosophical Journal
  +
|volume = 1
  +
|issue = 2
  +
|publisher = Dept. of Scholastic Philosophy, Queen's University of Belfast
  +
|location = Belfast
  +
|url = http://poiesis.nlx.com/display.cfm?clientId=0&advquery=toc.sect.ipj.1.2&infobase=postoc.nfo&softpage=GetClient42&view=browse
  +
|issn = 0266-9080
  +
|accessdate = 2007-12-03
  +
}}</ref> Said to have returned to Athens at the age of forty, Plato founded one of the earliest known organized schools in Western Civilization on a plot of land in the Grove of Hecademus or Academus.<ref>Huntington Cairns, Introduction to ''Plato: The Collected Dialogues'', p. xiii.</ref> The [[Academy]] was "a large enclosure of ground which was once the property of a citizen at Athens named [[Academus]]... some, however, say that it received its name from an ancient hero",<ref>Robinson, ''Arch. Graec.'' I i 16.</ref> and it operated until AD 529, when it was closed by [[Justinian I]] of [[Byzantium]], who saw it as a threat to the propagation of [[Christianity]]. Many intellectuals were schooled in the Academy, the most prominent one being [[Aristotle]].<ref>{{cite web
  +
|url = http://www.gradesaver.com/classicnotes/authors/about_aristotle.html
  +
|title = Biography of Aristotle
  +
|accessdate = 2007-12-03
  +
|work = ClassicNote
  +
|publisher = GradeSaver LLC
  +
}}</ref>
   
  +
===Plato and Socrates===
Another key distinction and theme in the Platonic corpus is the dichotomy between [[knowledge]] and [[opinion]], which foreshadow modern debates between [[David Hume]] and [[Immanuel Kant]], and has been taken up by [[postmodern]]ists and their opponents, more commonly as the distinction between the '[[objective]]' and the '[[subjective]]'.
 
  +
[[Image:Socrates and Plato.jpg|thumb|180px|left|Plato and [[Socrates]] in a medieval picture.]]
  +
Plato makes it clear, especially in his [[Apology (Plato)|''Apology of Socrates'']], that he was one of [[Socrates|Socrates']] devoted young followers. In that dialogue, Socrates is presented as mentioning Plato by name as one of those youths close enough to him to have been corrupted, if he were in fact guilty of corrupting the youth, and questioning why their fathers and brothers did not step forward to testify against him if he was indeed guilty of such a crime (33d-34a). Later, Plato is mentioned along with Crito, Critobolus, and Apollodorus as offering to pay a fine of 30 minas on Socrates' behalf, in lieu of the death penalty proposed by Meletus (38b). In the ''[[Phaedo]]'', the title character lists those who were in attendance at the prison on Socrates' last day, explaining Plato's absence by saying, "Plato was ill" (''Phaedo'' 59b).
   
  +
The relationship between Plato and Socrates is problematic, however. Aristotle, for example, attributes a different doctrine with respect to the [[Theory of forms|ideas]] to Plato and Socrates (''Metaphysics'' 987b1–11), but Plato never speaks in his own voice in his dialogues. In the [[Second Letter (Plato)|''Second Letter'']], it says, "no writing of Plato exists or ever will exist, but those now said to be his are those of a Socrates become beautiful and new" (341c); if the Letter is Plato's, the final qualification seems to call into question the dialogues' historical fidelity. In any case, [[Xenophon]] and [[Aristophanes]] seem to present a somewhat different portrait of Socrates than Plato paints. Some have called attention to the problem of taking Plato's Socrates to be his mouthpiece, given Socrates' reputation for irony.<ref>[[Leo Strauss]], ''The City and Man'' (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964), 50–1.</ref>
Even the story of the lost city or continent of [[Atlantis]] came to us as an illustrative story told by Plato in his ''[[Timaeus]]'' and ''[[Critias]]''.
 
   
  +
The precise relationship between Plato and Socrates remains an area of contention among scholars.
===Form and basis===
 
Plato wrote mainly in the form known as [[dialogue]]. In the early dialogues, several characters discuss a topic by asking questions of one another. Socrates figures prominently, and a lively, more disorganized form of ''[[elenchos]]''/[[dialectic]] is present; these are called the [[Socratic Dialogue]]s.
 
   
  +
==Philosophy==
The nature of these dialogues changed a great deal over the course of Plato's life. It is generally agreed that Plato's earlier works are more closely based on Socrates' thought, whereas his later writing increasingly breaks away from the views of his former teacher. In the middle dialogues, Socrates becomes a mouthpiece for Plato's own philosophy, and the question-and-answer style is more ''[[pro forma]]'': the main figure represents Plato and the minor characters have little to say except "yes", "of course" and "very true". The late dialogues read more like [[treatise]]s, and Socrates is often absent or quiet. It is assumed that while some of the early dialogues could be based on Socrates' actual conversations, the later dialogues were written entirely by Plato. The question of which, if any, of the dialogues are truly Socratic is known as the [[Socratic problem]].
 
  +
===Recurrent Themes===
  +
[[Image:Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg|thumb|upright|Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), a detail of ''[[The School of Athens]]''<!-- this should link to an article about the famous artwork -->, a fresco by [[Raphael]]. Aristotle gestures to the earth, representing his belief in knowledge through empirical observation and experience, while holding a copy of his ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' in his hand. Plato holds his ''[[Timaeus]]'' and gestures to the heavens, representing his belief in [[The Forms]].]]
  +
{{details|Aristotle's theory of universals}}
   
  +
Plato often discusses the father-son relationship and the "question" of whether a father's interest in his sons has much to do with how well his sons turn out. A boy in ancient Athens was socially located by his family identity, and Plato often refers to his characters in terms of their paternal and fraternal relationships. Socrates was not a family man, and saw himself as the son of his mother, who was apparently a midwife. A divine fatalist, Socrates mocks men who spent exorbitant fees on tutors and trainers for their sons, and repeatedly ventures the idea that good character is a gift from the gods. Crito reminds Socrates that orphans are at the mercy of chance, but Socrates is unconcerned. In the ''Theaetetus'', he is found recruiting as a disciple a young man whose inheritance has been squandered. Socrates twice compares the relationship of the older man and his boy lover to the father-son relationship (''Lysis'' 213a, ''Republic'' 3.403b), and in the ''Phaedo'', Socrates' disciples, towards whom he displays more concern than his biological sons, say they will feel "fatherless" when he is gone. Many dialogues, like these, suggest that man-boy love (which is "spiritual") is a wise man's substitute for father-son biology (which is "bodily").
The ostensible ''[[mise en scène]]'' of a dialogue distances both Plato and a given reader from the philosophy being discussed; one can choose between at least two options of [[perception]]: either to participate in the dialogues, in the [[idea]]s being discussed, or choose to see the [[content]] as expressive of the personalities contained within the work.
 
   
  +
In several dialogues, Socrates floats the idea that [[Knowledge]] is a matter of recollection, and not of learning, observation, or study.<ref>{{cite book | last = Baird | first = Forrest E. | authorlink = | coauthors = Walter Kaufmann | title = From Plato to Derrida | publisher = Pearson Prentice Hall | year = 2008 | location = Upper Saddle River, New Jersey | pages = | url = | doi = | id = | isbn = 0-13-158591-6 }}</ref> He maintains this view somewhat at his own expense, because in many dialogues, Socrates complains of his forgetfulness. Socrates is often found arguing that knowledge is not empirical, and that it comes from divine insight. He is quite consistent in believing in the immortality of the soul, and several dialogues end with long speeches imagining the [[afterlife]]. More than one dialogue contrasts knowledge and opinion, perception and [[reality]], [[nature]] and custom, and body and soul. The only contrast to this is his Parmenides.
The dialogue format also allows Plato to put unpopular opinions in the mouth of unsympathetic characters, such as [[Thrasymachus]] in ''[[Republic (Plato)|The Republic]]''.
 
   
  +
Several dialogues tackle questions about art: Socrates says that poetry is inspired by the [[muses]], and is not rational. He speaks approvingly of this, and other forms of divine madness (drunkenness, eroticism, and dreaming) in the ''[[Phaedrus (Plato)|Phaedrus]] ''(265a&ndash;c), and yet in the ''[[Republic (Plato)|''Republic'']]'' wants to outlaw Homer's great poetry, and laughter as well. In ''[[Ion (dialogue)|Ion]]'', Socrates gives no hint of the disapproval of Homer that he expresses in the ''Republic''. The dialogue ''Ion'' suggests that Homer's ''Iliad'' functioned in the ancient Greek world as the bible does today in the modern Christian world: as divinely inspired literature that can provide moral guidance, if only it can be properly interpreted.
==Metaphysics==
 
:''Main article: [[Platonic idealism]]''
 
   
  +
On politics and art, religion and science, justice and medicine, virtue and vice, crime and punishment, pleasure and pain, rhetoric and rhapsody, human nature and sexuality, love and wisdom, Socrates and his company of disputants had something to say.
'''Platonism''' has traditionally been interpreted as a form of metaphysical [[dualism]], sometimes referred to as '''Platonic''' or '''Exaggerated Realism'''. According to this reading, Plato's metaphysics divides the world into two distinct aspects: the intelligible world of "forms", and the perceptual world we see around us. The perceptual world consists of imperfect copies of the intelligible ''[[form]]s'' or ''[[idea]]s''. These forms are unchangeable and perfect, and are only comprehensible by the use of the intellect or understanding&mdash;i.e., a capacity of the mind that does not include [[perception|sense-perception]] or [[imagination]]. This division can also be found in [[Zoroaster|Zoroastrian]] philosophy, in which the dichotomy is referenced as the ''Minu'' (intelligence) and ''Giti'' (perceptual) worlds. The [[Zoroastrian]] ideal city, ''Shahrivar'', also exhibits certain similarities with Plato's ''[[Republic (dialogue)|Republic]]''. The existence and direction of influence here is uncertain; while [[Zoroaster]] lived well before Plato, few of the earliest writings of Zoroastrianism survive unaltered.
 
   
  +
===Metaphysics===
[[Image:PlatosCave.gif|thumb|right|350px|Illustrating Plato's Allegory of the Cave]]
 
  +
{{main|Platonic realism}}
In the ''Republic'' Books VI and VII, Plato uses a number of [[metaphor]]s to explain his metaphysical views: the [[Plato's metaphor of the sun|metaphor of the sun]], the well-known [[Plato's allegory of the cave|allegory of the cave]], and most explicitly, [[the divided line of Plato|the divided line]].
 
   
  +
"Platonism" is a term coined by scholars to refer to the intellectual consequences of denying, as Socrates often does, the reality of the material world. In several dialogues, most notably the Republic, Socrates inverts the common man's intuition about what is knowable and what is real. While most people take the objects of their senses to be real if anything is, Socrates is contemptuous of people who think that something has to be graspable in the hands to be real. In the ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]'', he says such people are "eu a-mousoi", an expression that means literally, "happily without the muses" (''Theaetetus'' 156a). In other words, such people live without the divine inspiration that gives him, and people like him, access to higher insights about reality.
Taken together, these metaphors convey a complex, and, in places, difficult theory: there is something called [[The Form of the Good]] (often interpreted as Plato's God), which is the ultimate object of [[knowledge]] and which, as it were, sheds light on all the other forms (i.e., [[universal (metaphysics)|universals]]: [[abstraction|abstract]] [[kind (word)|kinds]] and [[attribute]]s), and from which all other forms "emanate". The Form of the Good does this in somewhat the same way as the sun sheds light on, or makes visible and "generates" things, in the perceptual world. (See [[Plato's metaphor of the sun]])
 
   
  +
Socrates's idea that reality is unavailable to those who use their senses is what puts him at odds with the common man, and with common sense. Socrates says that he who sees with his eyes is blind, and this idea is most famously captured in his [[allegory of the cave]], and more explicitly in his description of [[the divided line of Plato|the divided line]]. The allegory of the cave (begins ''Republic'' 7.514a) is a paradoxical analogy wherein Socrates argues that the invisible world is the most intelligible ("noeton") and that the visible world ("(h)oraton") is the least knowable, and the most obscure. (This is exactly the opposite of what Socrates says to Euthyphro in the soothsayer's namesake dialogue. There, Socrates tells Euthyphro that people can agree on matters of logic and science, and are divided on moral matters, which are not so easily verifiable.)
In the perceptual world, the particular objects we see around us bear only a dim resemblance to the more ultimately real forms of Plato's intelligible world; it is as if we are seeing shadows of cut-out shapes on the walls of a cave, which are mere representations of the [[reality]] outside the cave, illuminated by the sun. (See [[Plato's allegory of the cave]])
 
   
  +
Socrates says in the ''Republic'' that people who take the sun-lit world of the senses to be good and real are living pitifully in a den of evil and ignorance. Socrates admits that few climb out of the den, or cave of ignorance, and those who do, not only have a terrible struggle to attain the heights, but when they go back down for a visit or to help other people up, they find themselves objects of scorn and ridicule.
We can imagine everything in the [[universe]] represented on a line of increasing reality; it is divided once in the middle, and then once again in each of the resulting parts. The first division represents that between the intelligible and the perceptual worlds. This is followed by a ''corresponding'' division in each of these worlds: the segment representing the perceptual world is divided into segments representing "real things" on the one hand, and shadows, reflections and representations on the other. Similarly, the segment representing the intelligible world is divided into segments representing [[first principle]]s and most general forms, on the one hand, and more derivative, "reflected" forms, on the other. (See [[the divided line of Plato]])
 
   
  +
According to Socrates, physical objects and physical events are "shadows" of their ideal or perfect forms, and exist only to the extent that they instantiate the perfect versions of themselves. Just as shadows are temporary, inconsequential epiphenomena produced by physical objects, physical objects are themselves fleeting phenomena caused by more substantial causes, the ideals of which they are mere instances. For example, Socrates thinks that perfect justice exists (although it is not clear where) and his own trial would be a cheap copy of it.
The form of government derived from this philosophy turns out to be one of a rigidly fixed [[hierarchy]] of [[hereditary]] [[social class]]es, in which the [[arts]] are mostly suppressed for the good of the state, the size of the city and its social classes is determined by mathematical formulae, and [[eugenics|eugenic]] measures are applied secretly by rigging the lotteries in which the right to reproduce is allocated. The exact relationship of such a government to the lofty philosophy presented in the book has been debated.
 
   
  +
The allegory of the cave (often said by scholars to represent Plato's own epistemology and metaphysics) is intimately connected to his political ideology (often said to also be Plato's own), that only people who have climbed out of the cave and cast their eyes on a vision of goodness are fit to rule. Socrates claims that the enlightened men of society must be forced from their divine contemplations and compelled to run the city according to their lofty insights. Thus is born the idea of the "philosopher-king", the wise person who accepts the power thrust upon him by the people who are wise enough to choose a good master. This is the main thesis of Socrates in the ''Republic'', that the most wisdom the masses can muster is the wise choice of a ruler.
Plato's metaphysics, and particularly its [[dualism]] between the intelligible and the perceptual, would inspire later [[Neoplatonism|Neoplatonic]] thinkers, such as [[Plotinus]] and [[Gnosticism|Gnostics]], and many other metaphysical realists. Although Platonistic philosophers like Plotinus rebuked Gnosticism (see Plotinus' [[Enneads]]). One reason being the Gnostic vilification of nature and Plato's [[Demiurge]] from ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]''. Plato also influenced [[Saint Justin Martyr]]. For more on Platonic realism in general, see [[Platonic realism]] and [[the Forms]].
 
   
  +
The word metaphysics derives from the fact that Aristotle's musings about divine reality came after ("meta") his lecture notes on his treatise on nature ("physics"). The term is in fact applied to Aristotle's own teacher, and Plato's "metaphysics" is understood as Socrates' division of reality into the warring and irreconcilable domains of the material and the spiritual. The theory has been of incalculable influence in the history of Western philosophy and religion.
Although this interpretation of Plato's writings (particularly the [[Republic]]) has enjoyed immense popularity throughout the long history of Western philosophy, it is also possible to interpret his suggestions more conservatively, favoring a more epistemological than metaphysical reading of such famous metaphors as the Cave and the Divided Line. There are obvious parallels between the Cave allegory and the life of Plato's teacher [[Socrates]] (who was killed in his attempt to "open the eyes" of the Athenians). This example reveals the dramatic complexity that often lies under the surface of Plato's writing (remember that in the [[Republic]], it is Socrates who relates the story.).
 
   
  +
===Theory of Forms===
==Epistemology==
 
{{main|Platonic epistemology}}
+
{{main | Theory of Forms }}
Plato also had some influential opinions on the nature of [[knowledge]] and [[learning]] which he propounded in the ''[[Meno (Plato)|Meno]]'', which began with the question of whether [[virtue]] can be taught, and proceeded to expound the concepts of [[recollection]], learning as the discovery of pre-existing knowledge, and [[right opinion]], opinions which are correct but have no clear justification.
 
   
  +
The Theory of Forms typically refers to Plato's belief that the material world as it seems to us is not the real world, but only a [[Plato's allegory of the cave|shadow of the real world]]. Plato spoke of forms in formulating [[Platonic realism|his solution]] to the [[problem of universals]]. The forms, according to Plato, are roughly speaking [[archetype]]s or [[Abstraction|abstract]] representations of the many [[type (metaphysics)|types]] and [[property (metaphysics)|properties]] (that is, of [[universal (metaphysics)|universals]]) of things we see all around us.
==The state==
 
Plato's philosophical views had many [[society|societal]] implications, especially on the idea of an ideal [[state]] or government. There is some discrepancy between his early and later views. Some of the most famous doctrines are contained in the ''Republic'' during his middle period.
 
   
  +
===Epistemology===
Plato asserts that societies have a tripartite class structure corresponding to the appetite/spirit/reason structure of the individual soul.
 
  +
{{main | Platonic epistemology}}
*''Productive'' (Workers) - The laborers, carpenters, plumbers, masons, merchants, farmers, ranchers, etc. These correspond to the "appetite" part of the soul.
 
*''Protective'' (Warriors) - Those who are adventurous, strong, brave, in love with danger; in the armed forces. These correspond to the "spirit" part of the soul.
 
*''Governing'' (Rulers) - Those who are intelligent, rational, self-controlled, in love with wisdom, well suited to make decisions for the community. These correspond to the "reason" part of the soul and are very few.
 
   
  +
Many have interpreted Plato as stating that [[knowledge]] is [[justified true belief]], an influential view which informed future developments in modern analytic epistemology. This interpretation is based on a reading of the ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]'' wherein Plato argues that belief is to be distinguished from knowledge on account of justification. Many years later, [[Edmund Gettier]] famously demonstrated the problems of the justified true belief account of knowledge. This interpretation, however, imports modern analytic and empiricist categories onto Plato himself and is better read on its own terms than as Plato's view.
According to this model, the principles of [[Athens|Athenian]] [[democracy]] (as it existed in his day) are rejected as only a few are fit to rule. Instead of rhetoric and persuasion, Plato says reason and wisdom should govern. This does not equate to [[tyranny]], [[despotism]] or [[oligarchy]], however. As Plato puts it:
 
   
  +
Really, in the ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]'', ''[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]'', ''[[Republic (dialogue)|Republic]]'', and the ''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]'' Plato himself associates knowledge with the apprehension of unchanging Forms and their relationships to one another (which he calls "expertise" in [[Dialectic]]). More explicitly, Plato himself argues in the ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus ]]'' that knowledge is always proportionate to the realm from which it is gained. In other words, if one derives their account of something experientially, because the world of sense is in flux, the views therein attained will be mere opinions. And opinions are characterized by a lack of necessity and stability. On the other hand, if one derives their account of something by way of the non-sensible forms, because these forms are unchanging, so too is the account derived from them. It is only in this sense that Plato uses the term "[[knowledge]]."
:"Until philosophers rule as kings or those who are now called kings and leading men genuinely and adequately philosophize, that is, until political power and philosophy entirely coincide, while the many natures who at present pursue either one exclusively are forcibly prevented from doing so, cities will have no rest from evils,... nor, I think, will the human race." (''Republic'' 473c-d)
 
   
  +
In the [[Meno (Plato)#Dialogue with Meno's slave|Meno]], Socrates uses a geometrical example to expound Plato's view that knowledge in this latter sense is acquired by [[Anamnesis|recollection]]. Socrates elicits a fact concerning a geometrical construction from a slave boy, who could not have otherwise known the fact (due to the slave boy's lack of education). The knowledge must be present, Socrates concludes, in an eternal, non-experiential form.
Plato describes these "philosopher kings" as "those who love the sight of truth" (''Republic'' 475c) and supports the idea with the analogy of a captain and his ship or a doctor and his medicine. Sailing and health are not things that everyone is qualified to practice by nature. A large part of the ''Republic'' then addresses how the educational system should be set up to produce these philosopher kings.
 
   
  +
===The State===
However, it must be taken into account that the ideal city outlined in the ''Republic'' is qualified by Socrates as the ideal ''luxurious'' city, examined to determine how it is that injustice and justice grow in a city (''Republic'' 372e). According to Socrates, the "true" and "healthy" city is instead the one first outlined in book II of the ''Republic'', 369c-372d, containing farmers, craftsmen, merchants and wage-earners, but lacking the guardian class of philosopher-kings as well as delicacies such as "perfumed oils, incense, prostitutes, and pastries", in addition to paintings, gold, ivory, couches, a multitude of occupations such as poets and hunters, and war.
 
  +
[[Image:POxy3679 Parts Plato Republic.jpg|thumb|''Papirus Oxyrhynchus'', with fragment of Plato's ''Republic'']]
  +
Plato's philosophical views had many societal implications, especially on the idea of an ideal [[state]] or government. There is some discrepancy between his early and later views. Some of the most famous doctrines are contained in the ''Republic'' during his middle period, as well as in the ''[[Laws (dialogue)|Laws]]'' and the ''[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]''. However, because Plato wrote dialogues, it is assumed that Socrates is often speaking for Plato. This assumption may not be true in all cases.
   
  +
Plato, through the words of Socrates, asserts that societies have a tripartite class structure corresponding to the appetite/spirit/reason structure of the individual soul. The appetite/spirit/reason stand for different parts of the body. The body parts symbolize the castes of society.<ref>{{cite book
==Platonic scholarship==
 
  +
| last =Gaarder
[[Image:Plato.png|thumb|"The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato." &mdash;[[Alfred North Whitehead]], Process and Reality, 1929]]
 
  +
| first =Jostein
  +
| authorlink = Jostein Gaarder
  +
| title =Sophie's World
  +
| publisher =Berkley
  +
| year =1996
  +
| location =New York City
  +
| pages =91
  +
}}</ref>
   
  +
* ''Productive'' Which represents the abdomen.(Workers) &mdash; the labourers, carpenters, plumbers, masons, merchants, farmers, ranchers, etc. These correspond to the "appetite" part of the soul.
Plato's thought is often compared with that of his most famous student, [[Aristotle]], whose reputation during the Western [[Middle Ages]] so completely eclipsed that of Plato that the [[Scholasticism|Scholastic]] philosophers referred to Aristotle as "the Philosopher". However, in the [[Byzantine Empire]], the study of Plato continued.
 
  +
* ''Protective'' Which represents the chest.(Warriors or Guardians) &mdash; those who are adventurous, strong and brave; in the armed forces. These correspond to the "spirit" part of the soul.
  +
* ''Governing'' Which represents the head. (Rulers or Philosopher Kings) &mdash; those who are intelligent, rational, self-controlled, in love with wisdom, well suited to make decisions for the community. These correspond to the "reason" part of the soul and are very few.
   
  +
According to this model, the principles of [[Athenian democracy]] (as it existed in his day) are rejected as only a few are fit to rule. Instead of rhetoric and persuasion, Plato says reason and wisdom should govern. As Plato puts it:
The Medieval scholastic philosophers did not have access to the works of Plato&mdash;nor the knowledge of [[Greek language|Greek]] needed to read them. Plato's original writings were essentially lost to Western civilization until they were brought from [[Constantinople]] in the century before its fall, by [[George Gemistos Plethon]]. Medieval scholars knew of Plato only through translations into [[Latin]] from the translations into [[Arabic language|Arabic]] by [[Iran|Persian]] and Arab scholars. These scholars not only translated the texts of the ancients, but expanded them by writing extensive [[commentary|commentaries]] and [[interpretation]]s on Plato's and [[Aristotle]]'s works (see [[Al-Farabi]], [[Avicenna]], [[Averroes]]).
 
   
  +
: "Until philosophers rule as kings or those who are now called kings and leading men genuinely and adequately philosophise, that is, until political power and philosophy entirely coincide, while the many natures who at present pursue either one exclusively are forcibly prevented from doing so, cities will have no rest from evils,... nor, I think, will the human race." (''Republic'' 473c-d)
Only in the [[Renaissance]], with the general resurgence of interest in classical civilization, did knowledge of Plato's philosophy become widespread again in the West. Many of the greatest early modern scientists and artists who broke with [[Scholasticism]] and fostered the flowering of the Renaissance, with the support of the Plato-inspired [[Lorenzo de Medici]], saw Plato's philosophy as the basis for progress in the arts and sciences. By the [[19th century]], Plato's reputation was restored, and at least on par with Aristotle's.
 
  +
[[Image:Plato i sin akademi, av Carl Johan Wahlbom (ur Svenska Familj-Journalen).png|thumb|260px|Plato in his academy, drawing after a painting by Swedish painter Carl Johan Wahlbom]]
   
  +
Plato describes these "philosopher kings" as "those who love the sight of truth" (''Republic'' 475c) and supports the idea with the analogy of a captain and his ship or a doctor and his medicine. Sailing and health are not things that everyone is qualified to practice by nature. A large part of the ''Republic'' then addresses how the educational system should be set up to produce these philosopher kings.
Notable Western philosophers have continued to draw upon Plato's work since that time. Plato's influence has been especially strong in mathematics and the sciences. It inspired the greatest advances in logic since Aristotle, due to [[Gottlob Frege]] and his followers [[Kurt Gödel]], [[Alonzo Church]], and [[Alfred Tarski]], the last of whom summarized his approach by reversing Asistotle's famous declaration of sedition from the Academy: ''Inimicus Plato, sed magis inimica falsitas''; Plato is an enemy, but falsehood is yet a greater enemy. [[Albert Einstein]] drew on Plato's understanding of an immutable reality that underlies the flux of appearances for his objections to the probabilistic picture of the physical universe propounded by [[Niels Bohr]] in his interpretation of [[quantum mechanics]]. Conversely, thinkers that diverged from [[ontology|ontological]] models and [[moral]] ideals in their own philosophy, have tended to disparage Platonism from more or less informed perspectives. Thus [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] attacked Plato's moral and political theories, [[Martin Heidegger]] expatiated upon Plato's alleged obfuscation of ''[[Being]]''', and [[Karl Popper]] argued in ''[[The Open Society and Its Enemies]]'' ([[1945]]) that Plato's proposal for a government system in ''[[Republic (Plato)|The Republic]]'' was prototypically [[totalitarianism|totalitarian]].
 
   
  +
However, it must be taken into account that the ideal city outlined in the ''Republic'' is qualified by Socrates as the ideal ''luxurious'' city, examined to determine how it is that injustice and justice grow in a city (''Republic'' 372e). According to Socrates, the "true" and "healthy" city is instead the one first outlined in book II of the ''Republic'', 369c&ndash;372d, containing farmers, craftsmen, merchants, and wage-earners, but lacking the guardian class of philosopher-kings as well as delicacies such as "perfumed oils, incense, prostitutes, and pastries", in addition to paintings, gold, ivory, couches, a multitude of occupations such as poets and hunters, and war.
==Bibliography==
 
Plato's writings (most of them [[dialogues]]) have been published in several fashions; this has led to several conventions regarding the naming and referencing of Plato's texts.
 
   
  +
In addition, the ideal city is used as an image to illuminate the state of one's soul, or the [[Free will|will]], [[reason]], and [[Interpersonal attraction|desire]]s combined in the human body. Socrates is attempting to make an image of a rightly ordered human, and then later goes on to describe the different kinds of humans that can be observed, from tyrants to lovers of money in various kinds of cities. The ideal city is not promoted, but only used to magnify the different kinds of individual humans and the state of their soul. However, the [[philosopher king]] image was used by many after Plato to justify their personal political beliefs. The philosophic soul according to Socrates has reason, will, and desires united in virtuous harmony. A philosopher has the [[moderate]] love for [[wisdom]] and the [[courage]] to act according to wisdom. Wisdom is [[knowledge]] about the [[Goodness and value theory|Good]] or the right relations between all that [[Existence|exist]]s.
Those works ascribed to Plato that have a separate Wikipedia article can be found in [[:Category:Dialogues of Plato]]
 
   
  +
Wherein it concerns states and rulers, Plato has made interesting arguments. For instance he asks which is better - a bad democracy or a country reigned by a tyrant. He argues that it is better to be ruled by a bad tyrant (since then there is only one person committing bad deeds) than be a bad democracy (since here all the people are now responsible for such actions.)
===By tetralogy===
 
One tradition regarding the arrangement of Plato's texts is according to [[tetralogy|tetralogies]]. This scheme is ascribed by [[Diogenes Laertius]] to an ancient scholar and court astrologer to [[Tiberius]] named [[Thrasyllus]].
 
   
  +
According to Plato, a state which is made up of different kinds of souls, will overall decline from an [[aristocracy]] (rule by the best) to a [[timocracy]] (rule by the honorable), then to an [[oligarchy]] (rule by the few), then to a [[democracy]] (rule by the people), and finally to [[tyranny]] (rule by one person, rule by a tyrant){{Fact|date=April 2008}}<!-- More than a bare reference to the Republic is necessary here; it is disputed that Plato actually believed this -->.
In the list below, works by Plato are marked (1) if there is no consensus among scholars as to whether Plato is the author, and (2) if scholars generally agree that Plato is ''not'' the author of the work. Unmarked works are assumed to have been written by Plato.
 
   
====Tetralogies====
+
===Unwritten Doctrine===
  +
For a long time Plato's unwritten doctrine<ref>Rodriguez- Grandjean, Pablo. [http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Anci/AnciRodr.htm ''Philosophy and Dialogue: Plato's Unwritten Doctrines from a Hermeneutical Point of View''], Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, in Boston, Massachusetts from August 10-15, 1998.</ref><ref>Reale, Giovanni, and Catan, John R., ''A History of Ancient Philosophy'', SUNY Press, 1990. ISBN 0791405168. Cf. p.14 and onwards.</ref><ref>Krämer, Hans Joachim, and Catan, John R., ''Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics: A Work on the Theory of the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines of Plato with a Collection of the Fundamental Documents'', (Translated by John R. Catan), SUNY Press, 1990. ISBN 0791404331, Cf. pp.38-47</ref> had been considered unworthy of attention. Most of the books on Plato seem to diminish its importance. Nevertheless the first important witness who mentions its existence is [[Aristotle]], who in his ''[[Physics (Aristotle)|Physics]]'' (209 b) writes: "It is true, indeed, that the account he gives there [i.e. in ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]''] of the participant is different from what he says in his so-called ''unwritten teaching'' (ἄγραφα δόγματα)." The term ''ἄγραφα δόγματα'' literally means ''unwritten doctrine'' and it stands for the most fundamental metaphysical teaching of Plato which he disclosed only to his most trusted fellows and kept secret from the public.
*I. ''[[Euthyphro]]'', ''[[Apology (Plato)|(The) Apology (of Socrates)]]'', ''[[Crito]]'', ''[[Phaedo]]''
 
*II. ''[[Cratylus]]'', ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]'', ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]'', ''[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]''
 
*III. ''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]'', ''[[Philebus]]'', ''[[Symposium (Plato dialogue)|(The) Symposium]]'', ''[[Phaedrus (dialogue)|Phaedrus]]''
 
*IV. ''[[Alcibiades (dialogues)|First Alcibiades]]'' (1), ''[[Alcibiades (dialogues)|Second Alcibiades]]'' (2), ''[[Hipparchus (dialogue)|Hipparchus]]'' (2), ''[[Rival Lovers|(The) (Rival) Lovers]]'' (2)
 
*V. ''[[Theages]]'' (2), ''[[Charmides (dialogue)|Charmides]]'', ''[[Laches (dialogue)|Laches]]'', ''[[Lysis (dialogue)|Lysis]]''
 
*VI. ''[[Euthydemus (dialogue)|Euthydemus]]'', ''[[Protagoras (dialogue)|Protagoras]]'', ''[[Gorgias (dialogue)|Gorgias]]'', ''[[Meno]]''
 
*VII. ''[[Hippias (dialogues)|(Greater) Hippias (major)]]'' (1), ''[[Hippias (dialogues)|(Lesser) Hippias (minor)]]'', ''[[Ion (dialogue)|Ion]]'', ''[[Menexenus]]''
 
*VIII. ''[[Clitophon]]'' (1), ''[[Republic (dialogue)|(The) Republic]]'', ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]'', ''[[Critias (dialogue)|Critias]]''
 
*IX. ''[[Minos (dialogue)|Minos]]'' (2), ''[[Laws (dialogue)|(The) Laws]]'', ''[[Epinomis]]'' (2), ''[[Letters (Plato)|Letters]]'' (1)
 
   
  +
The reason for not revealing it to everyone is partially discussed in [[Phaedrus (dialogue)|Phaedrus]] (276 c) where Plato criticizes the written transmission of knowledge as faulty, favoring instead the spoken [[logos]]: "he who has knowledge of the just and the good and beautiful ... will not, when in earnest, write them in ink, sowing them through a pen with words which cannot defend themselves by argument and cannot teach the truth effectually." The same argument is repeated in Plato's ''[[Seventh Letter (Plato)|Seventh Letter]]'' (344 c): "every serious man in dealing with really serious subjects carefully avoids writing." In the same letter he writes (341 c): "I can certainly declare concerning all these writers who claim to know the subjects which I seriously study ... there does not exist, nor will there ever exist, any treatise of mine dealing therewith." Such secrecy is necessary in order not "to expose them to unseemly and degrading treatment" (344 d).
====Works not in tetralogies====
 
The remaining works were transmitted under Plato's name, most of them already considered spurious in antiquity:
 
*''[[Axiochus]]'' (2), ''[[Definitions (Plato)|Definitions]]'' (2), ''[[Demodocus (dialogue)|Demodocus]]'' (2), ''[[Epigrams (Plato)|Epigrams]]'', ''[[Eryxias]]'' (2), ''[[Halcyon (dialogue)|Halcyon]]'' (2), ''[[On Justice]]'' (2), ''[[On Virtue]]'' (2), ''[[Sisyphus (dialogue)|Sisyphus]]'' (2)
 
   
  +
It is however said that Plato once disclosed this knowledge to the public in his lecture ''On the Good'' (Περὶ τἀγαθοῦ), in which the Good (τὸ ἀγαθόν) is identified with the One (the Unity, τὸ ἕν), the fundamental ontological principle. The content of this lecture has been transmitted by several witnesses, among others [[Aristoxenus]] who describes the event in the following words: "Each came expecting to learn something about the things which are generally considered good for men, such as wealth, good health, physical strength, and altogether a kind of wonderful happiness. But when the mathematical demonstrations came, including numbers, geometrical figures and astronomy, and finally the statement Good is One seemed to them, I imagine, utterly unexpected and strange; hence some belittled the matter, while others rejected it." [[Simplicius of Cilicia|Simplicius]] quotes [[Alexander of Aphrodisias]] who states that "according to Plato, the first principles of everything, including the Forms themselves are One and Indefinite Duality (ἡ ἀόριστος δυάς) which he called Large and Small (τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν) ... one might also learn this from Speusippus and Xenocrates and the others who were present at Plato's lecture on the Good"
===Stephanus pagination===
 
The usual system for making unique references to sections of the text by Plato derives from a [[16th century]] edition of Plato's works by [[Henri Estienne|Henricus Stephanus]]. An overview of Plato's writings according to this system can be found in the [[Stephanus pagination]] article.
 
   
  +
Their account is in full agreement with [[Aristotle]]'s description of Plato's metaphysical doctrine. In ''[[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Metaphysics]]'' he writes: "Now since the Forms are the causes of everything else, he [i.e. Plato] supposed that their elements are the elements of all things. Accordingly the material principle is the Great and Small [i.e. the Dyad], and the essence is the One (τὸ ἕν), since the numbers are derived from the Great and Small by participation in the One" (987 b). "From this account it is clear that he only employed two causes: that of the essence, and the material cause; for the Forms are the cause of the essence in everything else, and the One is the cause of it in the Forms. He also tells us what the material substrate is of which the Forms are predicated in the case of sensible things, and the One in that of the Forms - that it is this the duality (the Dyad, ἡ δυάς), the Great and Small (τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν). Further, he assigned to these two elements respectively the causation of good and of evil" (988 a).
===Chronology===
 
The exact order in which Plato's dialogues were written is not known, nor is the extent to which some might have been later revised and rewritten. However, there is enough information internal to the dialogues to form a rough chronology. The dialogues are normally grouped into three fairly distinct periods, with a few of them considered transitional works, and some just difficult to place.
 
   
  +
The most important aspect of this interpretation of Plato's metaphysics is the continuity between his teaching and the neoplatonic interpretation of [[Plotinus]]<ref>[[Plotinus]] describes this in the last part of his final [[Enneads|Ennead]] (VI, 9) entitled ''On the Good, or the One'' (Περὶ τἀγαθοῦ ἢ τοῦ ἑνός). Jens Halfwassen states in [http://ccat.sas.upenn.edu/bmcr/2006/2006-08-16.html Der Aufstieg zum Einen] (2006) that "Plotinus' ontology - which should rather be called Plotinus' henology - is a rather accurate philosophical renewal and continuation of Plato's unwritten doctrine, i.e. the doctrine rediscovered by Krämer and Gaiser."</ref> or [[Ficino]]<ref>In one of his letters (Epistolae 1612) [[Ficino]] writes: "The main goal of the divine Plato ... is to show one principle of things which he called the One (τὸ ἕν)", cf. Marsilio Ficino, [http://books.google.com/books?id=KuYYAAAAIAAJ Briefe des Mediceerkreises], Berlin, 1926, p. 147.</ref> which has been considered errorneous by many but may in fact have been directly influenced by oral transmission of Plato's doctrine. The first scholar who recognized the importance of the unwritten doctrine of Plato was [[Heinrich Gomperz]] who described it in his speech during the 7th [[International Congress of Philosophy]] in 1930.<ref>H. Gomperz, ''Plato's System of Philosophy'', in: G. Ryle (ed.), [http://books.google.com/books?id=zN0MAAAAIAAJ ''Proceedings of the Seventh International Congress of Philosophy], London 1931, pp. 426-431. Reprinted in: H. Gomperz, [http://books.google.com/books?id=ox81AAAAIAAJ ''Philosophical Studies''], Boston, 1953, pp. 119-24.</ref> All the sources related to the ἄγραφα δόγματα have been collected by Konrad Gaiser and published as ''Testimonia Platonica''.<ref>K. Gaiser, ''Testimonia Platonica. Le antiche testimonianze sulle dottrine non scritte di Platone'', Milan, 1998. First published as ''Testimonia Platonica. Quellentexte zur Schule und mündlichen Lehre Platons'' as an appendix to Gaiser's ''Platons Ungeschriebene Lehre'', Stuttgart, 1963.</ref> These sources have subsequently been interpreted by scholars from the german ''Tübingen School'' such as Hans Joachim Krämer or Thomas A. Szlezák.<ref>For a bried description of the problem see for example K. Gaiser, [http://www.ingentaconnect.com/content/brill/phr/1980/00000025/F0020001/art00002 ''Plato's enigmatic lecture "On the Good"''], Phronesis 25 (1980), pp. 5-37. A detailed analysis is given by Krämer in his [http://books.google.com/books?id=T2k6edyBklwC ''Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics: A Work on the Theory of the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines of Plato With a Collection of the Fundamental Documents''], Albany: SUNY Press, 1990. Another good description is by Giovanni Reale: [http://books.google.com/books?id=xmsGAAAACAAJ ''Toward a New Interpretation of Plato''], Washington, D.C.: CUA Press, 1997. Reale summarizes the results of his research in [http://books.google.com/books?id=QfvRZSlJd3MC ''A History of Ancient Philosophy: Plato and Aristotle''], Albany: SUNY Press, 1990. However the most complete analysis of the consequences of such an approach is given by Thomas A. Szlezak in his fundamental [http://books.google.com/books?id=x34szlJIRIgC ''Reading Plato''], New York: Routledge, 1999. Another supporter of this interpretation is the german philosopher [[Karl Albert]], cf. [http://books.google.com/books?id=5D4NAAAAIAAJ Griechische Religion und platonische Philosophie], Hamburg, 1980 or [http://books.google.com/books?id=VFvoAAAACAAJ Einführung in die philosophische Mystik], Darmstadt, 1996. [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]] is also sympathetic towards it, cf. J. Grondin, [http://www.philo.umontreal.ca/prof/documents/GadamerandtheTubingenSchool2006.doc06.doc Gadamer and the Tübingen School] and [[Gadamer]]'s 1968 article ''Plato's Unwritten Dialectic'' reprinted in his [http://books.google.com/books?hl=en&lr=&id=HfNUhz7T6ocC Dialogue and Dialectic]. [[Gadamer]]'s final position on the subject is stated in his introduction to [http://books.google.com/books?id=wNzXAQAACAAJ La nuova interpretazione di Platone. Un dialogo tra Hans-Georg Gadamer e la scuola di Tubinga], Milano 1998.</ref>
Many of the positions in this ordering are still highly disputed.
 
   
  +
==Works==
====Early Dialogues====
 
  +
[[Image:Plato Republic 1713.jpg|thumb|180px|Plato's ''The Republic'', Latin edition cover, 1713]]
Socrates figures in all of these, and they are considered the most faithful representations of the historical Socrates; hence they are also called the [[Socratic dialogues]]. Most of them consist of Socrates discussing a subject, often an ethical one (friendship, piety) with a friend or with someone presumed to be an expert on it. Through a series of questions he will show that they don't apparently understand it at all. This period also includes several pieces surrounding the trial and execution of Socrates.
 
  +
Thirty-five dialogues and thirteen letters have traditionally been ascribed to Plato, though modern scholarship doubts the authenticity of at least some of these. Plato's writings have been published in several fashions; this has led to several conventions regarding the naming and referencing of Plato's texts.
   
  +
The usual system for making unique references to sections of the text by Plato derives from a 16th century edition of Plato's works by [[Henri Estienne|Henricus Stephanus]]. An overview of Plato's writings according to this system can be found in the [[Stephanus pagination]] article.
*[[Apology (Plato)|Apology]]
 
*[[Crito]]
 
*[[Charmides (dialogue)|Charmides]]
 
*[[Laches (dialogue)|Laches]]
 
*[[Lysis (dialogue)|Lysis]]
 
*[[Euthyphro]]
 
*[[Menexenus]]
 
*[[Lesser Hippias]]
 
*[[Ion (dialogue)|Ion]]
 
   
  +
One tradition regarding the arrangement of Plato's texts is according to [[tetralogy|tetralogies]]. This scheme is ascribed by [[Diogenes Laertius]] to an ancient scholar and court astrologer to [[Tiberius]] named [[Thrasyllus of Mendes|Thrasyllus]].
The following are variously considered transitional or middle period dialogues:
 
   
  +
In the list below, works by Plato are marked (1) if there is no consensus among scholars as to whether Plato is the author, and (2) if scholars generally agree that Plato is ''not'' the author of the work. Unmarked works are assumed to have been written by Plato.
*[[Gorgias (dialogue)|Gorgias]]
 
*[[Protagoras (dialogue)|Protagoras]]
 
*[[Meno]]
 
   
  +
<div style="-moz-column-count:2; column-count:2;">
===Middle Dialogues===
 
  +
* I. ''[[Euthyphro]]'', ''[[Apology (Plato)|(The) Apology (of Socrates)]]'', ''[[Crito]]'', ''[[Phaedo]]''
Late in the early dialogues Plato's Socrates actually begins supplying answers to some of the questions he asks, or putting forth positive doctrines. This is generally seen as the first appearance of Plato's own views. The first of these, that goodness is wisdom and that no one does evil willingly, was perhaps Socrates' own view. What becomes most prominent in the middle dialogues is the idea that knowledge comes of grasping unchanging forms or essences, paired with the attempts to investigate such essences. The immortality of the soul, and specific doctrines about justice, truth, and beauty, begin appearing here. The [[Symposium]] and the [[Republic (dialogue)|Republic]] are considered the centrepieces of Plato's middle period.
 
  +
* II. ''[[Cratylus (dialogue)|Cratylus]]'', ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]'', ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]'', ''[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]''
  +
* III. ''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]'', ''[[Philebus]]'', ''[[Symposium (Plato dialogue)|(The) Symposium]]'', ''[[Phaedrus (dialogue)|Phaedrus]]''
  +
* IV. ''[[First Alcibiades]]'' (1), ''[[Second Alcibiades]]'' (2), ''[[Hipparchus (dialogue)|Hipparchus]]'' (2), ''[[Rival Lovers|(The) (Rival) Lovers]]'' (2)
  +
* V. ''[[Theages]]'' (2), ''[[Charmides (dialogue)|Charmides]]'', ''[[Laches (dialogue)|Laches]]'', ''[[Lysis (dialogue)|Lysis]]''
  +
* VI. ''[[Euthydemus (dialogue)|Euthydemus]]'', ''[[Protagoras (dialogue)|Protagoras]]'', ''[[Gorgias (dialogue)|Gorgias]]'', ''[[Meno]]''
  +
* VII. ''[[Hippias major|(Greater) Hippias (major)]]'' (1), ''[[Hippias minor|(Lesser) Hippias (minor)]]'', ''[[Ion (dialogue)|Ion]]'', ''[[Menexenus]]''
  +
* VIII. ''[[Clitophon]]'' (1), ''[[Republic (dialogue)|(The) Republic]]'', ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]'', ''[[Critias (dialogue)|Critias]]''
  +
* IX. ''[[Minos (dialogue)|Minos]]'' (2), ''[[Laws (dialogue)|(The) Laws]]'', ''[[Epinomis]]'' (2), ''[[Epistles (Plato)|Epistles]]'' (1).
  +
</div>
   
  +
The remaining works were transmitted under Plato's name, most of them already considered spurious in antiquity, and so were not included by Thrasyllus in his tetralogical arrangement. These works are labelled as ''Notheuomenoi'' ("spurious") or ''Apocrypha''.
*[[Euthydemus (dialogue)|Euthydemus]]
 
  +
* ''[[Axiochus]]'' (2), ''[[Definitions (Plato)|Definitions]]'' (2), ''[[Demodocus (dialogue)|Demodocus]]'' (2), ''[[Epigrams (Plato)|Epigrams]]'', ''[[Eryxias]]'' (2), ''[[Halcyon (dialogue)|Halcyon]]'' (2), ''[[On Justice]]'' (2), ''[[On Virtue]]'' (2), ''[[Sisyphus (dialogue)|Sisyphus]]'' (2).
*[[Cratylus]]
 
  +
*[[Phaedo]]
 
  +
=== Plato's Dialogues ===
*[[Phaedrus (dialogue)|Phaedrus]]
 
  +
The exact order in which Plato's dialogues were written is not known, nor is the extent to which some might have been later revised and rewritten.
*[[Symposium (Plato dialogue)|Symposium]]
 
  +
*[[Republic (dialogue)|Republic]]
 
  +
[[Lewis Campbell]] was the first<ref>p. 9, [[John Burnet (classicist)|John Burnet]], ''Platonism'', University of California Press 1928.</ref> to make exhaustive use of [[stylometry]] to prove objectively that the ''Critias'', ''Timaeus'', ''Laws'', ''Philebus'', ''Sophist'', and ''Statesman'' were all clustered together as a group, while the ''Parmenides'', ''Phaedrus'', ''Republic'', and ''Theaetetus'' belong to a separate group, which must be earlier (given [[Aristotle]]'s statement in his ''Politics''<ref>[http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0058&layout=&loc=2.1264b 1264b24-27]</ref> that the ''Laws'' was written after the ''Republic''; cf. [[Diogenes Laertius]] ''Lives'' 3.37). What is remarkable about Campbell's conclusions is that, in spite of all the stylometric studies that have been conducted since his time, perhaps the only chronological fact about Plato's works that can now be said to be ''proven'' by stylometry is the fact that ''Critias'', ''Timaeus'', ''Laws'', ''Philebus'', ''Sophist'', and ''Statesman'' are the latest of Plato's dialogues, the others earlier.<ref>p. xiv, J. Cooper (ed.), ''Plato: Complete Works'', Hackett 1997.</ref>
*[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]
 
  +
*[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]
 
  +
Increasingly in the most recent Plato scholarship, writers are skeptical of the notion that the order of Plato's writings can be established with any precision,<ref>Richard Kraut, [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato/ "Plato"], ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', accessed 24 June 2008; Malcolm Schofield (1998, 2002), "Plato", in E. Craig (Ed.), ''Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/A088, accessed 24 June 2008; Christopher Rowe, "Interpreting Plato", in H. Benson (ed.), ''A Companion to Plato'', Blackwell 2006.</ref> though Plato's works are still often characterized as falling at least roughly into three groups.<ref>T. Brickhouse & N. Smith, [http://www.iep.utm.edu/p/plato.htm "Plato"], ''The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', accessed 24 June 2008.</ref> The following represents one such devision which is relatively common.<ref>See W. Guthrie, ''A History of Greek Philosophy'', vol. 4, Cambridge University Press 1975; G. Vlastos, ''Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher'', Cambridge University Press 1991; T. Penner, "Socrates and the Early Dialogues", in R. Kraut (ed.), ''The Cambridge Companion to Plato'', Cambridge University Press 1992; C. Kahn, ''Plato and the Socratic Dialogue'', Cambridge University Press 1996; G. Fine, ''Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the Soul'', Oxford University Press 1999.</ref> It should, however, be kept in mind that many of the positions in the ordering are still highly disputed, and also that the very notion that Plato's dialogues can or should be "ordered" is by no means universally accepted.
  +
  +
====Early dialogues====
  +
Socrates figures in all of these, and they are considered the most faithful representations of the historical Socrates; hence they are also called the [[Socratic dialogues]]. Most of them consist of Socrates discussing a subject, often an ethical one (friendship, piety) with a friend or with someone presumed to be an expert on it. Through a series of questions he will show that apparently they do not understand it at all. It is left to the reader to figure out if "he" really understands "it". This makes these dialogues "indirect" teachings.
  +
* ''[[Apology (Plato)|Apology]]''
  +
* ''[[Charmides (dialogue)|Charmides]]''
  +
* ''[[Crito]]''
  +
* ''[[Euthyphro]]''
  +
* ''[[Ion (dialogue)|Ion]]''
  +
* ''[[Laches (dialogue)|Laches]]''
  +
* ''[[Lesser Hippias]]''
  +
* ''[[Lysis (dialogue)|Lysis]]''
  +
* ''[[Menexenus (dialogue)|Menexenus]]''
  +
* ''[[Protagoras (dialogue)|Protagoras]]'' is often considered one of the last of these "earlier" dialogues.
  +
  +
The following are often considered "transitional" or "pre-middle" dialogues:
  +
* ''[[Euthydemus (dialogue)|Euthydemus]]''
  +
* ''[[Gorgias (dialogue)|Gorgias]]''
  +
* ''[[Meno]]''
  +
  +
==== Middle dialogues ====
  +
Late in the early dialogues Plato's Socrates actually begins supplying answers to some of the questions he asks, or putting forth positive doctrines. This is generally seen as the first appearance of Plato's own views. The first of these, that goodness is wisdom and that no one does evil willingly, was perhaps Socrates' own view. What becomes most prominent in the middle dialogues is the idea that knowledge comes of grasping unchanging forms or essences, paired with the attempts to investigate such essences. The immortality of the soul, and specific doctrines about justice, truth, and beauty, begin appearing here. The [[Symposium (Plato dialogue)|Symposium]] and the [[Republic (dialogue)|Republic]] are considered the centrepieces of Plato's middle period. The [[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]] and [[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]] are often considered to come late in this period and transitional to the next, as they seem to treat the Theory of Forms critically (''Parmenides'') or not at all (''Theaetetus'').
  +
* ''[[Cratylus (dialogue)|Cratylus]]''
  +
* ''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]''
  +
* ''[[Phaedo]]''
  +
* ''[[Phaedrus (dialogue)|Phaedrus]]''
  +
* ''[[Republic (Plato)|Republic]]''
  +
* ''[[Symposium (Plato dialogue)|Symposium]]''
  +
* ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]''
   
 
====Late dialogues====
 
====Late dialogues====
  +
[[Image:Plato Timaeus.jpg|thumb|right|180px|Early modern latin [[incunabulum]] of Plato's ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]'', 1491]]
The [[Parmenides]] presents a series of criticisms of the Theory of Forms which are widely taken to indicate Plato's abandonment of the doctrine. In most of the remaining dialogues the theory is absent (the [[Timaeus]] is an important, and hence controversially placed, exception). Socrates is either absent or a minor figure in the discussion.
 
   
  +
The ''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]'' presents a series of criticisms of the theory of Forms which are widely taken to indicate Plato's abandonment of the doctrine. Some recent publications (e.g., Meinwald (1991)) have challenged this characterisation. In most of the remaining dialogues the theory is either absent or at least appears under a different guise in discussions about kinds or classes of things (the ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]'' may be an important, and hence controversially placed, exception). Socrates is either absent or a minor figure in the discussion. An apparently new method for doing dialectic known as "collection and division" is also featured, most notably in the ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]'' and ''[[Statesman]]'', explicitly for the first time in the ''[[Phaedrus (dialogue)|Phaedrus]]'', and possibly in the ''[[Philebus]]''. A basic description of collection and division would go as follows: interlocutors attempt to discern the similarities and differences among things in order to get clear idea about what they in fact are. One understanding, suggested in some passages of the ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]'', is that this is what philosophy is always in the business of doing, and is doing even in the early dialogues.
*[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]
 
*[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]
 
*[[Philebus]]
 
*[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]
 
*[[Critias (dialogue)|Critias]]
 
*[[Laws (dialogue)|Laws]]
 
   
  +
The late dialogues are also an important place to look for Plato's mature thought on most of the issues dealt with in the earlier dialogues. There is much work still to be done by scholars on the working out of what these views are. The later works are agreed to be difficult and challenging pieces of philosophy. On the whole they are more sober and logical than earlier works, but may hold out the promise of steps towards a solution to problems which were systematically laid out in prior works.
===Loeb Classical Library===
 
  +
* ''[[Critias (dialogue)|Critias]]''
[[James Loeb]] provided a very popular edition of Plato's works, still in print in the [[21st century]]: see [[Loeb Classical Library#Plato]] for how Plato's works were named in Loeb's publications.
 
  +
* ''[[Laws (dialogue)|Laws]]''
  +
* ''[[Philebus]]''
  +
* ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]''
  +
* ''[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]''
  +
* ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]''
  +
  +
===Narration of the dialogues===
  +
Plato never presents himself as a participant in any of the dialogues, and with the exception of the ''[[Apology (Plato)|Apology]]'', there is no suggestion that he heard any of the dialogues firsthand. Some dialogues have no narrator but have a pure "dramatic" form (examples: ''[[Meno]]'', ''[[Gorgias (dialogue)|Gorgias]]'', ''[[Phaedrus (Plato)|Phaedrus]]'', ''[[Crito]]'', ''[[Euthyphro]]''), some dialogues are narrated by Socrates, wherein he speaks in first person (examples: ''[[Lysis (dialogue)|Lysis]]'', ''[[Charmides (dialogue)|Charmides]]'', ''[[Republic (Plato)|Republic]]''). One dialogue, ''[[Protagoras (dialogue)|Protagoras]]'', begins in dramatic form but quickly proceeds to Socrates' narration of a conversation he had previously with the sophist for whom the dialogue is named; this narration continues uninterrupted till the dialogue's end.
  +
  +
[[Image:Anselm Feuerbach 003.jpg|thumb|260px|[[Symposium (Plato)|Plato's Symposium]] ([[Anselm Feuerbach]], 1873)]]
  +
The three dialogues, ''[[Phaedo]]'', ''[[Symposium (Plato)|Symposium]]'', and ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]'', also begin in dramatic form but then proceed to virtually uninterrupted narration by followers of Socrates, and all, apparently, based on their distant memory or secondhand reports. ''Phaedo'', an account of Socrates' final conversation and hemlock drinking, is narrated by Phaedo to Echecrates in a foreign city many years after the execution took place. The ''Symposium'' is narrated by Apollodorus, a Socratic disciple, apparently to Glaucon. Apollodorus assures his listener that he is recounting the story, which took place when he himself was an infant, not from his own memory, but as remembered by Aristodemus, who told him the story years ago. In the beginning of the ''Theaetetus'' (142c-143b), [[Euclid of Megara|Euclides]] says that he compiled the conversation from notes he took based on what Socrates told him of his conversation with the title character. The rest of the ''Theaetetus'' is presented as a "book" written in dramatic form and read by one of Euclides' slaves (143c). Some scholars take this as an indication that Plato had by this date wearied of the narrated form.<ref>sect. 177, [[John Burnet (classicist)|J. Burnet]], ''Greek Philosophy'', MacMillan 1950.</ref> With the exception of the ''Theaetetus'', Plato gives no explicit indication as to how these orally transmitted conversations came to be written down. Other dialogues, such as the ''Phaedo'', ''Symposium'', and ''Parmenides'', do suggest that such conversations were faithfully recalled and transmitted by Socrates' followers.<ref>pp. 23-24, [[W. K. C. Guthrie]], ''Socrates'', Cambridge 1971.</ref>
  +
  +
===Trial of Socrates===
  +
{{see main|Trial of Socrates}}
  +
The trial of Socrates is the central, unifying event of the great Platonic dialogues. Because of this, Plato's ''[[Apology (Plato)|Apology]]'' is perhaps the most often read of the dialogues. In the ''Apology'', Socrates tries to dismiss rumors that he is a [[sophism|sophist]] and defends himself against charges of disbelief in the gods and corruption of the young. Socrates insists that long-standing slander will be the real cause of his demise, and says the legal charges are essentially false. Socrates famously denies being wise, and explains how his life as a philosopher was launched by the [[Oracle at Delphi]]. He says that his quest to resolve the riddle of the oracle put him at odds with his fellow man, and that this is the reason he has been mistaken for a menace to the city-state of Athens.
  +
  +
===Unity and Diversity of the Dialogues===
  +
If Plato's important dialogues do not refer to Socrates' execution explicitly, they allude to it, or use characters or themes that play a part in it. Five dialogues foreshadow the trial: In the ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]'' (210d) and the ''[[Euthyphro]]'' (2a&ndash;b) Socrates tells people that he is about to face corruption charges. In the ''[[Meno]]'' (94e&ndash;95a), one of the men who brings legal charges against Socrates, [[Anytus]], warns him about the trouble he may get into if he does not stop criticizing important people. In the ''[[Gorgias]]'', Socrates says that his trial will be like a doctor prosecuted by a cook who asks a jury of children to choose between the doctor's bitter medicine and the cook's tasty treats (521e&ndash;522a). In the ''[[Republic]]'' (7.517e), Socrates explains why an enlightened man (presumably himself) will stumble in a courtroom situation. The ''Apology'' is Socrates' defense speech, and the ''[[Crito]]'' and ''[[Phaedo]]'' take place in prison after the conviction. In the ''[[Protagoras]]'', Socrates is a guest at the home of [[Callias III|Callias]], son of [[Hipponicus]], a man whom Socrates disparages in the ''Apology'' as having wasted a great amount of money on sophists' fees.
  +
  +
Two other important dialogues, the ''[[Symposium (Plato)|Symposium]]'' and the ''[[Phaedrus (Plato)|Phaedrus]]'', are linked to the main storyline by characters. In the ''Apology'' (19b, c), Socrates says [[Aristophanes]] slandered him in a comic play, and blames him for causing his bad reputation, and ultimately, his death. In the ''Symposium'', the two of them are drinking together with other friends. The character Phaedrus is linked to the main story line by character (Phaedrus is also a participant in the ''Symposium'' and the ''Protagoras'') and by theme (the philosopher as divine emissary, etc.) The ''Protagoras'' is also strongly linked to the ''Symposium'' by characters: all of the formal speakers at the ''Symposium'' (with the exception of Aristophanes) are present at the home of Callias in that dialogue. [[Charmides]] and his guardian [[Critias]] are present for the discussion in the ''Protagoras''. Examples of characters crossing between dialogues can be further multiplied. The ''Protagoras'' contains the largest gathering of Socratic associates.
  +
  +
In the dialogues for which Plato is most celebrated and admired, Socrates is concerned with human and political virtue, has a distinctive personality, and friends and enemies who "travel" with him from dialogue to dialogue. This is not to say that Socrates is consistent: a man who is his friend in one dialogue may be an adversary or subject of his mockery in another. For example, Socrates praises the wisdom of Euthyphro many times in the ''[[Cratylus (dialogue)|Cratylus]]'', but makes him look like a fool in the ''[[Euthyphro]]''. He disparages sophists generally, and [[Prodicus]] specifically in the ''[[Apology (Plato)|Apology]]'', yet tells Theaetetus in his namesake dialogue that he admires Prodicus and has directed many pupils to him. In [[Cratylus]] (384b-c), Socrates says that he studied with Cratylus, and took his one-[[drachma]] course because he could not afford the full fifty-drachma course. Socrates' ideas are also not consistent within or between or among dialogues.
  +
  +
===Platonic Scholarship===
  +
[[Image:0042MC.jpg|thumb|"The safest general characterisation of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato." ([[Alfred North Whitehead]], ''[[Process and Reality]]'', 1929).]]
  +
  +
Plato's thought is often compared with that of his most famous student, [[Aristotle]], whose reputation during the Western [[Middle Ages]] so completely eclipsed that of Plato that the [[Scholasticism|Scholastic]] philosophers referred to Aristotle as "the Philosopher". However, in the [[Byzantine Empire]], the study of Plato continued.
  +
  +
The Medieval scholastic philosophers did not have access to the works of Plato, nor the knowledge of [[Greek language|Greek]] needed to read them. Plato's original writings were essentially lost to Western civilization until they were brought from [[Constantinople]] in the century before its fall, by [[George Gemistos Plethon]].{{Fact|date=January 2008}}<!-- Please source the claim these claims. --> Medieval scholars knew of Plato only through translations into [[Latin]] from the translations into [[Arabic language|Arabic]] by [[Iran|Persian]] and Arab scholars. These scholars not only translated the texts of the ancients, but expanded them by writing extensive [[Close reading|commentaries]] and [[interpretation]]s on Plato's and [[Aristotle]]'s works (see [[Al-Farabi]], [[Avicenna]], [[Averroes]]).
  +
  +
Only in the [[Renaissance]], with the general resurgence of interest in classical civilization, did knowledge of Plato's philosophy become widespread again in the West. Many of the greatest early modern scientists and artists who broke with [[Scholasticism]] and fostered the flowering of the Renaissance, with the support of the Plato-inspired [[Lorenzo de Medici]], saw Plato's philosophy as the basis for progress in the arts and sciences. By the 19th century, Plato's reputation was restored, and at least on par with Aristotle's.
  +
  +
Notable Western philosophers have continued to draw upon Plato's work since that time. Plato's influence has been especially strong in mathematics and the sciences. He helped to distinguish between [[pure mathematics|pure]] and [[applied mathematics]] by widening the gap between "arithmetic", now called [[Number Theory]] and "logistic", now called [[arithmetic]]. He regarded logistic as appropriate for business men and men of war who "must learn the art of numbers or he will not know how to array his troops," while arithmetic was appropriate for philosophers "because he has to arise out of the sea of change and lay hold of true being."<ref>{{cite book|first=Carl B. |last=Boyer |authorlink=Carl Benjamin Boyer |title=A History of Mathematics |edition=Second Edition |publisher=John Wiley & Sons, Inc. |year=1991 |isbn=0471543977|chapter=The age of Plato and Aristotle|pages=86|quote=Plato is important in the history of mathematics largely for his role as inspirer and director of others, and perhaps to him is due the sharp distinction in ancient Greece between arithmetic (in the sense of the theory of numbers) and logistic (the technique of computation). Plato regarded logistic as appropriate for the businessman and for the man of war, who "must learn the art of numbers or he will not know how to array his troops." The philosopher, on the other hand, must be an arithmetician "because he has to arise out of the sea of change and lay hold of true being."}}</ref> Plato's resurgence further inspired some of the greatest advances in logic since Aristotle, primarily through [[Gottlob Frege]] and his followers [[Kurt Gödel]], [[Alonzo Church]], and [[Alfred Tarski]]; the last of these summarised his approach by reversing Aristotle's famous declaration of sedition from the ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' (1096a15: ''Amicus Plato sed magis amica veritas'' - "Plato is a friend, but truth is a greater friend") to ''Inimicus Plato sed magis inimica falsitas'' ("Plato is an enemy, but falsehood is a greater enemy"). [[Albert Einstein]] drew on Plato's understanding of an immutable reality that underlies the flux of appearances for his objections to the probabilistic picture of the physical universe propounded by [[Niels Bohr]] in his interpretation of [[quantum mechanics]].{{Fact|date=March 2008}} Conversely, thinkers that diverged from [[ontology|ontological]] models and [[moral]] ideals in their own philosophy, have tended to disparage Platonism from more or less informed perspectives. Thus [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] attacked Plato's moral and political theories, [[Martin Heidegger]] argued against Plato's alleged obfuscation of ''[[Being]]'', and [[Karl Popper]] argued in ''[[The Open Society and Its Enemies]]'' (1945) that Plato's alleged proposal for a government system in the ''Republic'' was prototypically [[totalitarianism|totalitarian]]. [[Leo Strauss]] is considered by some as the prime thinker involved in the recovery of Platonic thought in its more political, and less metaphysical, form. Deeply influenced by Nietzsche and Heidegger, Strauss nonetheless rejects their condemnation of Plato and looks to the dialogues for a solution to what all three thinkers acknowledge as 'the crisis of the West.'
  +
  +
{{academia
  +
|teachers='''[[Socrates]]'''
  +
|students=
  +
[[Amyclus of Heraclea]]<br/>
  +
[[Aristonymus]]</br>
  +
'''[[Aristotle]]'''</br>
  +
[[Axiothea of Phlius]]</br>
  +
[[Callippus of Athens]]</br>
  +
[[Coriscus of Scepsis]]</br>
  +
[[Demetrius of Amphipolis]]</br>
  +
[[Dion of Syracuse]]</br>
  +
[[Erastus of Scepsis]]</br>
  +
[[Euaeon of Lampsacus]]</br>
  +
[[Eudoxus of Cnidus]]</br>
  +
[[Heraclides of Aenus]]</br>
  +
[[Heraclides of Pontus]]</br>
  +
[[Hermias of Atarneus]]</br>
  +
[[Hestiaeus of Perinthus]]</br>
  +
[[Hippothales of Athens]]</br>
  +
[[Lastheneia of Mantinea]]</br>
  +
[[Philippus of Opus]]</br>
  +
[[Phormio]]</br>
  +
[[Python of Aenus]]</br>
  +
[[Speusippus|Speusippus of Athens]]</br>
  +
[[Timolaus of Cyzicus]]</br>
  +
[[Theophrastus]]</br>
  +
[[Xenocrates|Xenocrates of Chalcedon]]</br>
  +
}}
   
 
==See also==
 
==See also==
{{wikiquote}}
 
* [[List_of_publications_in_philosophy#Western philosophy|Important publications in Western philosophy]]
 
* [[Mitchell Miller]]
 
 
* [[Alexander Nehamas]]
 
* [[Alexander Nehamas]]
* [[Neoplatonism]]
+
* [[Cambridge Platonists]]
  +
* [[Eric A. Havelock]]
  +
* [[Jacob Klein (philosopher)]]
 
* [[Platonic love]]
 
* [[Platonic love]]
* [[Platonism]]
+
* [[Platonic Realism]]
* [[Plotinus]]
+
* [[Mitchell Miller]]
  +
* [[Seth Benardete]]
*[http://www.philosophicalsociety.com/Archives/Plato%20And%20The%20Theory%20Of%20Forms.htm Theory of Forms]
 
  +
* [[Seventh Letter (Plato)]]
  +
  +
==Notes==
  +
<div class="references-small">
  +
'''a.''' {{Note_label|A|a|none}} The [[grammarian]] [[Apollodorus]] argues in his ''Chronicles'' that Plato was born in the first year of the eighty-eighth Olympiad (427 BC), on the seventh day of the month [[Thargelion]]; according to this tradition the god [[Apollo]] was born this day.<ref name="LaII">Diogenes Laertius, ''Life of Plato'', II</ref> According to another biographer of him, [[Neanthes of Cyzicus|Neanthes]], Plato was eighty-four years of age at his death.<ref name="LaII" /> If we accept Neanthes' version, Plato was younger than [[Isocrates]] by six years, and therefore he was born in the second year of the 87th [[Ancient Olympic Games|Olympiad]], the year Pericles died (429 BC).<ref>F.W. Nietzsche, ''Werke'', 32</ref> According to the ''[[Suda]],'' Plato was born in [[Aegina]] in the 88th Olympiad amid the preliminaries of the [[Peloponnesian war]], and he lived 82 years.<ref name="Suda">{{cite encyclopedia|title=Plato|encyclopedia=Suda}}</ref> [[Sir Thomas Browne]] also believes that Plato was born in the 88th Olympiad.<ref name="BrXII">T. Browne, ''Pseudodoxia Epidemica'', XII</ref> [[Renaissance]] [[Platonist]]s celebrated Plato's birth on [[November 7]].<ref name="N1">D. Nails, ''The Life of Plato of Athens'', 1</ref> Wilamowitz-Moellendorff estimates that Plato was born when Diotimos was [[archon#Ancient Greece|archon eponymous]], namely between [[July 29]] 428 BC and [[July 24]] 427 BC.<ref name="W46">U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, ''Plato'', 46</ref> Greek philologist Ioannis Kalitsounakis believes that the philosopher was born on [[May 26]] or 27 427 BC, while [[Jonathan Barnes]] regards 428 BC as year of Plato's birth.<ref name="HBr">{{cite encyclopedia|title=Plato|encyclopedia=Encyclopaedia Britannica|year=2002}}<br>*{{cite encyclopedia|title=Plato|encyclopedia=Encyclopaedic Dictionary The Helios Volume V (in Greek)|year=1952}}</ref> For her part, Debra Nails asserts that the philosopher was born in 424/423 BC.<ref name="N1" />
  +
  +
'''b.''' {{Note_label|B|b|none}} Diogenes Laertius mentions that Plato "was born, according to some writers, in Aegina in the house of Phidiades the son of Thales". Diogenes mentions as one of his sources the ''Universal History'' of [[Favorinus]]. According to Favorinus, Ariston, Plato's family, and his family were sent by Athens to settle as [[cleruchy|cleruch]]s (colonists retaining their Athenian citizenship), on the island of Aegina, from which they were expelled by the [[Sparta]]ns after Plato's birth there.<ref name="LaIII">Diogenes Laertius, ''Life of Plato'', III</ref> Nails points out, however, that there is no record of any Spartan expulsion of Athenians from Aegina between 431-411 BC.<ref name="NA54">D. Nails, "Ariston", 54</ref> On the other hand, at the [[Peace of Nicias]], Aegina was silently left under Athens' control, and it was not until the summer of 411 that the Spartans overran the island.<ref name="Th5.18.8.92">Thucydides, [[s:History of the Peloponnesian War/Book 5#5:18|5.18]]<br>* Thucydides, [[s:History of the Peloponnesian War/Book 8#8:92|8.92]]</ref> Therefore, Nails concludes that "perhaps Ariston was a cleruch, perhaps he went to Aegina in 431, and perhaps Plato was born on Aegina, but none of this enables a precise dating of Ariston's death (or Plato's birth).<ref name="NA54" /> Aegina is regarded as Plato's place of birth by Suda as well.<ref name="Suda" />
  +
  +
'''c.''' {{Note_label|C|c|none}} ''Plato'' was a common name, of which 31 instances are known at Athens alone.<ref name="GT">W. K. C. Guthrie, ''A History of Greek Philosophy'', IV, 10<br>* L. Tarán, ''Plato's Alleged Epitaph'', 61</ref>
  +
  +
</div>
  +
  +
==Notes==
  +
{{reflist|2}}
   
 
==References==
 
==References==
  +
===Primary sources (Greek and Roman)===
*{{Book reference | Author=Cooper, John M. & Hutchinson, D. S. (Eds.) | Title=Plato: Complete Works | Publisher=Hackett Publishing Co., Inc | Year=1997 | ID=ISBN 0872203492}}
 
  +
<div class="references-small">
*{{Book reference | Author=Hamilton, Edith & Cairns, Huntington (Eds.) | Title=The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Including the Letters | Publisher=Princeton Univ. Press | Year=1961 | ID=ISBN 0691097186}}
 
  +
* [[Apuleius]], ''De Dogmate Platonis'', I. ''See original text in [http://www.thelatinlibrary.com/apuleius/apuleius.dog1.shtml Latin Library]''.
*{{Book reference | Author=Jackson, Roy | Title=Plato: A Beginner's Guide | Publisher=London: Hoder & Stroughton | Year=2001 | ID=ISBN 0-340-80385-1}}
 
  +
* [[Aristophanes]], ''[[The Wasps]]''. ''See original text in [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus:text:1999.01.0043:line=1 Perseus program]''.
*{{Book reference | Author=Kraut, Richard (Ed.) | Title=The Cambridge Companion to Plato | Publisher=Cambridge University Press | Year=1993 | ID=ISBN 0521436109}}
 
  +
* [[Aristotle]], ''[[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Metaphysics]]. ''See original text in [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus:text:1999.01.0051:book=1:section=980a Perseus program]''.
*{{Book reference | Author=Melchert, Norman | Title=The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy | Publisher=McGraw Hill | Year=2002 | ID=ISBN 0195175107}}
 
  +
* [[Cicero]], ''De Divinatione'', I. ''See original text in [http://www.thelatinlibrary.com/cicero/divinatione1.shtml Latin library]''.
*[[Oxford University Press]] publishes scholarly editions of Plato's Greek texts in the ''[[Oxford Classical Texts]]'' series, and some translations in the ''Clarendon Plato Series''.
 
  +
* [[Diogenes Laertius]], ''Life of Plato''. ''Translated by [http://www.classicpersuasion.org/pw/diogenes/dlplato.htm C.D. Yonge]''.
*[[Harvard University Press]] publishes the hardbound series ''[[Loeb_Classical_Library#Plato|Loeb Classical Library]]'', containing Plato's works in [[Greek language|Greek]], with English translations on facing pages.
 
  +
* {{Cite wikisource|Charmides|Plato}}. See original text in [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus:text:1999.01.0175:text=Charm.:section=153a Perseus program].
*[http://www.lesbelleslettres.com Les Belles Lettres] also publishes Plato's complete works in Greek with French translations.
 
  +
* {{Cite wikisource|Gorgias|Plato}}. ''See original text in [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus:text:1999.01.0177:text=Gorg.:section=447a Perseus program]''.
*{{Book reference | Author=Smith, William. | Title=Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology | Publisher=University of Michigan/Online version | Year=1867 - original }}
 
  +
* Plato, ''Parmenides''. ''See original text in [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus:text:1999.01.0173:text=Parm.:section=126a Perseus program]''.
  +
* {{Cite wikisource|The Republic|Plato}}. See original text in [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0168 Perseus program].
  +
* [[Image:wikisource-logo.svg|15px]] [[Plutarch]], [[s:Lives/Pericles|Pericles]]. See original text in [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus:text:1999.01.0181:text=Per.:chapter=39:section=1 Perseus program].
  +
* {{Cite wikisource|History of the Peloponnesian War|[[Thucydides]]}}, V, VIII. ''See original text in [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0199 Perseus program]''.
  +
* [[Xenophon]], ''[[Memorabilia (Xenophon)|Memorabilia]]''. ''See original text in [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus:text:1999.01.0207:book=1:chapter=1:section=1 Perseus program]''.
  +
</div>
  +
  +
===Secondary sources===
  +
<div class="references-small">
  +
* {{cite book|last=Browne|first=Sir Thomas|title=[http://penelope.uchicago.edu/pseudodoxia/pseudo412.html#b26 Pseudodoxia Epidemica] |year=1646-1672|unused_data=|IV.xii}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Guthrie|first=W.K.C.|title=A History of Greek Philosophy: Volume 4, Plato: The Man and His Dialogues: Earlier Period |year=1986 | publisher=Cambridge University Press| isbn=0-521-31101-2}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Kahn|first=Charles H.|title=Plato and the socratic dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form |year=2004 | publisher=Cambridge University Press| isbn=0-521-64830-0| chapter=The Framework}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Nails|first=Debra|title=A Companion to Plato edited by Hugh H. Benson |year=2006 | publisher=Blackwell Publishing| isbn=1-405-11521-1|chapter=The Life of Plato of Athens}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Nails|first=Debra|title=The People of Plato: A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics |year=2002 | publisher=Hackett Publishing| isbn=0-872-20564-9|chapter=Ariston/Perictione}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Nietzsche|first=Friedrich Wilhelm|title=Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe (in German) |year=1967 | publisher=Walter de Gruyter| isbn=3-110-13912-X|chapter=Vorlesungsaufzeichnungen}}
  +
* {{cite journal|last=Notopoulos|first=A.|title=The Name of Plato|journal=Classical Philology|volume=34|issue=No.2|pages=135–145|month=April | year=1939|publisher=The University of Chicago Press|doi=10.1086/362227}}
  +
* {{cite encyclopedia|title=Plato|encyclopedia=Encyclopaedia Britannica|year=2002}}
  +
* {{cite encyclopedia|title=Plato|encyclopedia=Encyclopaedic Dictionary The Helios Volume XVI (in Greek)|year=1952}}
  +
* {{cite encyclopedia|title=[http://www.stoa.org/sol-bin/search.pl?search_method=QUERY&login=guest&enlogin=guest&page_num=1&user_list=LIST&searchstr=Plato&field=hw_eng&num_per_page=25&db=REAL Plato]|encyclopedia=Suda|date=10th century}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Smith|first=William|title=Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology |year=1870 | url=http://www.ancientlibrary.com/smith-bio/2725.html| chapter=Plato}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Tarán|first=Leonardo|title=Collected Papers 1962-1999 |year=2001 | publisher=Brill Academic Publishers | isbn= 9-004-12304-0. }}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Taylor|first=Alfred Edward|title=Plato: The Man and his Work |year=2001 | publisher=Courier Dover Publications| isbn=0-486-41605-4}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Wilamowitz-Moellendorff|first=Ulrich von|title=Plato: his Life and Work (translated in Greek by Xenophon Armyros |year=2005 (first edition 1917) | publisher=Kaktos| isbn=960-382-664-2}}
  +
</div>
  +
  +
==Further reading==
  +
* [[Ed. R.E. Allen|Allen, R.E.]] (2006). ''Studies in Plato's Metaphysics II''. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-18-6
  +
* [[David Ambuel|Ambuel, David]] (2006). ''Image and Paradigm in Plato's Sophist''. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-004-9
  +
* Bakalis, Nikolaos (2005). ''Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments'', Trafford Publishing ISBN 1-4120-4843-5
  +
* {{cite book| last=Barrow| first=Robin| year=2007| title=Plato: Continuum Library of Educational Thought| publisher=Continuum| isbn=0-8264-8408-5}}
  +
* Cadame, Claude (1999). ''Indigenous and Modern Prespectives on Tribal Initiation Rites: Education According to Plato'', pp. 278-312, in Padilla, Mark William (editor), [http://books.google.com/books?id=-0JVScga2oYC&printsec=frontcover&dq=rites+of+passage+in+ancient+greece "Rites of Passage in Ancient Greece: Literature, Religion, Society"], [[Bucknell University]] Press, 1999. ISBN 0-8387-5418-X
  +
* {{cite book | author=Cooper, John M. & Hutchinson, D. S. (Eds.) | title=Plato: Complete Works | publisher=[[Hackett Publishing Company]], Inc | year=1997 | isbn=0-87220-349-2}}
  +
* [[J. Angelo Corlett|Corlett, J. Angelo]] (2005). ''Interpreting Plato's Dialogues''. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-02-5
  +
* {{cite book | author=Durant, Will | title=The Story of Philosophy | publisher=Simon & Schuster | year=1926 | isbn=0-671-69500-2}}
  +
* [[Jacques Derrida|Derrida, Jacques]] (1972). ''La dissémination'', Paris: Seuil. (esp. cap.: ''La Pharmacie de Platon'', 69-199) ISBN 2-02-001958-2
  +
* {{cite book|author=Field, G.C. (Guy Cromwell)|title=The Philosophy of Plato|edition=2nd ed. with an appendix by R. C. Cross.|location=London|publisher=Oxford University Press|year=1969|isbn=0198880405}}
  +
* Fine, Gail (2000). ''Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology'' Oxford University Press, USA, ISBN 0-19-875206-7
  +
* {{cite book|author=Garvey, James |title=Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books |publisher=Continuum |year=2006, |isbn=0826490530}}
  +
* [[W. K. C. Guthrie|Guthrie, W. K. C.]] (1986). ''A History of Greek Philosophy (Plato - The Man & His Dialogues - Earlier Period)'', Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-31101-2
  +
* [[W. K. C. Guthrie|Guthrie, W. K. C.]] (1986). ''A History of Greek Philosophy (Later Plato & the Academy)'' Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-31102-0
  +
* Havelock, Eric (2005). ''Preface to Plato (History of the Greek Mind)'', Belknap Press, ISBN 0-674-69906-8
  +
* {{cite book | author=Hamilton, Edith & Cairns, Huntington (Eds.) | title=The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Including the Letters | publisher=Princeton Univ. Press | year=1961 | isbn=0-691-09718-6}}
  +
*Irwin, Terence (1995). ''Plato's Ethics'', Oxford University Press, USA, ISBN 0-19-508645-7
  +
* {{cite book | author=Jackson, Roy | title=Plato: A Beginner's Guide | location=London | publisher=Hoder & Stroughton | year=2001 | isbn=0-340-80385-1}}
  +
* {{cite book | author=Kochin, Michael S. | title=Gender and Rhetoric in Plato’s Political Thought | publisher=Cambridge Univ. Press | year=2002 | isbn=0-521-80852-9}}
  +
* {{cite book | author=Kraut, Richard (Ed.) | title=The Cambridge Companion to Plato | publisher=Cambridge University Press | year=1993 | isbn=0-521-43610-9}}
  +
* {{cite book | author=Krämer, Hans Joachim | title=[http://books.google.com/books?id=T2k6edyBklwC Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics] | publisher=SUNY Press | year=1990 | isbn=0-791-40433-1}}
  +
* [[Suzanne Lilar|Lilar, Suzanne]] (1954), Journal de l'analogiste, Paris, Éditions Julliard; Reedited 1979, Paris, Grasset. Foreword by [[Julien Gracq]]
  +
* [[Suzanne Lilar|Lilar, Suzanne]] (1963), ''Le couple'', Paris, Grasset. Translated as ''Aspects of Love in Western Society'' in 1965, with a foreword by Jonathan Griffin London, Thames and Hudson.
  +
* [[Suzanne Lilar|Lilar, Suzanne]] (1967) ''A propos de Sartre et de l'amour '', Paris, Grasset.
  +
* {{cite book | author=Lundberg, Phillip | title=Tallyho - The Hunt for Virtue: Beauty,Truth and Goodness Nine Dialogues by Plato: Pheadrus, Lysis, Protagoras, Charmides, Parmenides, Gorgias, Theaetetus, Meno & Sophist | publisher=Authorhouse | year=2005 | isbn=1-4184-4977-6}}
  +
* {{cite book | author=Melchert, Norman | title=The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy | publisher=McGraw Hill | year=2002 | isbn=0-19-517510-7}}
  +
* {{cite book | author=Meinwald, Constance Chu | title=Plato's Parmenides | publisher=Oxford University Press | year=1991 | isbn=0-19-506445-3 }}
  +
* [[Mitchell Miller|Miller, Mitchell]] (2004). ''The Philosopher in Plato's Statesman''. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-16-2
  +
* [[Richard D. Mohr|Mohr, Richard D.]] (2006). ''God and Forms in Plato - and other Essays in Plato's Metaphysics''. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-01-8
  +
* Moore, Edward (2007). ''Plato''. Philosophy Insights Series. Tirril, Humanities-Ebooks. ISBN 978-1-84760-047-9
  +
* Nightingale, Andrea Wilson. (1995). [http://books.google.com/books?id=n3MeQikAp00C&printsec=frontcover&source=gbs_summary_r&cad=0 "Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy"], Cambridge University Press. ISBN 052148264X
  +
* {{cite book | author=Reale, Giovanni | title=[http://books.google.com/books?id=QfvRZSlJd3MC A History of Ancient Philosophy: Plato and Aristotle] | publisher=SUNY Press | year=1990 | isbn=0-791-40516-8 }}
  +
* {{cite book | author=Reale, Giovanni | title=[http://books.google.com/books?id=xmsGAAAACAAJ Toward a New Interpretation of Plato] | publisher=CUA Press | year=1997 | isbn=0-813-20847-5 }}
  +
* {{cite book | author=[[John Sallis|Sallis, John]] | title=Being and Logos: Reading the Platonic Dialogues | publisher=Indiana University Press | year=1996 | isbn=0-253-21071-2 }}
  +
* {{cite book | author=[[John Sallis|Sallis, John]] | title=Chorology: On Beginning in Plato's "Timaeus" | publisher=Indiana University Press | year=1999 | isbn=0-253-21308-8 }}
  +
* [[Kenneth M. Sayre|Sayre, Kenneth M.]] (2006). ''Plato's Late Ontology: A Riddle Resolved''. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-09-4
  +
* [[T. K. Seung|Seung, T. K. ]] (1996). ''Plato Rediscovered: Human Value and Social Order''. Rowman and Littlefield. ISBN: 0847681122
  +
* {{cite book | author=Szlezak, Thomas A. | title=[http://books.google.com/books?id=x34szlJIRIgC Reading Plato] | publisher=Routledge | year=1999 | isbn=0-415-18984-5 }}
  +
* Taylor, A. E. (2001). ''Plato: The Man and His Work'', Dover Publications, ISBN 0-486-41605-4
  +
* [[Gregory Vlastos|Vlastos, Gregory]] (1981). ''Platonic Studies'', Princeton University Press, ISBN 0-691-10021-7
  +
* [[Gregory Vlastos|Vlastos, Gregory]] (2006). ''Plato's Universe - with a new Introducution by Luc Brisson'', Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-13-1
  +
* [[Oxford University Press]] publishes scholarly editions of Plato's Greek texts in the ''[[Oxford Classical Texts]]'' series, and some translations in the ''Clarendon Plato Series''.
  +
* [[Harvard University Press]] publishes the hardbound series ''[[Loeb Classical Library#Plato|Loeb Classical Library]]'', containing Plato's works in [[Greek language|Greek]], with English translations on facing pages.
  +
* [[Thomas Taylor (neoplatonist)|Thomas Taylor]] has translated Plato's complete works.
  +
* {{cite book | author=Smith, William. | title=Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology | publisher=University of Michigan/Online version | year=1867 &mdash; original }}
  +
*''Aspects of antiquity: Discoveries and Controversies'' by M.I. Finley, issued 1969 by The Viking Press, Inc.
  +
*''Interpreting Plato: The Dialogues as Drama'' by James A. Arieti, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc. ISBN 0-8476-7662-5
   
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
{{commons|Plato}}
+
{{Wikisourcelang|en|Author:Plato|Plato}}
  +
{{wikisourcelang|el|Πλάτων|Platon}}
* {{gutenberg author| id=Plato | name=Plato}}
 
  +
{{wikiquote}}
** [http://www.gutenberg.org/catalog/world/authrec?fk_authors=93 Works by Plato] at [[Project Gutenberg]]
 
  +
{{Commonscat|Plato}}
** [http://www.gutenberg.org/catalog/world/authrec?fk_authors=688 Spurious and doubtful works] at [[Project Gutenberg]]
 
  +
* Works available on-line:
* {{PerseusAuthor|Plato}}
 
  +
** {{PerseusAuthor|Plato}} - Greek & English hyperlinked text
* [http://www.learnoutloud.com/Content/Topic-Pages/Plato-Out-Loud/47 Plato Audio Bibliography]
 
  +
** [http://oll.libertyfund.org/index.php?option=com_staticxt&staticfile=show.php%3Ftitle=166&Itemid=99999999 Works of Plato (Jowett, 1892)]
*[http://www.philosophicalsociety.com/Archives/Plato%20And%20The%20Theory%20Of%20Forms.htm "Plato & The Theory of Forms," at Philosophical Society.com]
 
  +
** {{gutenberg author | id=Plato | name=Plato}}
*Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
 
  +
*** [http://www.gutenberg.org/catalog/world/authrec?fk_authors=688 Spurious and doubtful works] at [[Project Gutenberg]]
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato/ Plato]
 
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-ethics/ Plato's Ethics]
+
** [http://www.davemckay.co.uk/philosophy/plato Complete Works on The Philosophy Pages]
  +
** [http://www.ellopos.net/elpenor/greek-texts/ancient-greece/plato/default.asp Plato complete works, annotated and searchable, at ELPENOR]
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-friendship/ Friendship and Eros]
 
  +
** [http://librivox.org/euthyphro-by-plato/ Euthyphro] LibriVox recording
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-metaphysics/ Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology]
 
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-utopia/ Plato on Utopia]
+
** [http://librivox.org/ion-by-plato/ Ion] LibriVox recording
  +
**[http://ourworld.compuserve.com/homepages/jsuebersax/tetral.htm Quick Links to Plato's Dialogues (English, Greek, French, Spanish)]
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-rhetoric/ Rhetoric and Poetry]
 
   
  +
* Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
*Other articles
 
  +
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato/ Plato]
**[http://www.ellopos.net/elpenor/greek-texts/ancient-greece/guthrie-plato.asp Excerpt from W.K.C. Guthrie, ''A History of Greek Philosophy, vol. IV, Plato: the man and his dialogues, earlier period'', Cambridge University Press, 1989, pp. 8-38]
 
  +
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-ethics/ Plato's Ethics]
**[http://www.philosophicalsociety.com/Archives/The%20Platonic%20Conception%20of%20Philosophy.htm "The Platonic Conception of Philosophy"]
 
  +
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-friendship/ Friendship and Eros]
  +
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-metaphysics/ Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology]
  +
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-utopia/ Plato on Utopia]
  +
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-rhetoric/ Rhetoric and Poetry]
   
  +
* Other Articles:
[[Category:427 BC births]]
 
  +
** [http://www.ellopos.net/elpenor/greek-texts/ancient-greece/guthrie-plato.asp Excerpt from W.K.C. Guthrie, ''A History of Greek Philosophy, vol. IV, Plato: the man and his dialogues, earlier period'', Cambridge University Press, 1989, pp. 8-38]
[[Category:347 BC deaths]]
 
  +
** [http://plato-dialogues.org/plato.htm Website on Plato and his works: Plato and his dialogues by Bernard Suzanne]
[[Category:Ancient Athenians]]
 
  +
** [http://journal.ilovephilosophy.com/Article/Are-there-really-Platonic-forms-/53 Are there really Platonic forms?]
[[Category:Ancient Greek philosophers]]
 
  +
** [http://www.worldfuturefund.org/wffmaster/Reading/Quotes/plato.htm "Plato and Totalitarianism: A Documentary Study"]
[[Category:Platonism]]
 
  +
** [http://www.hermes-press.com/Perennial_Tradition/academy_index.htm The New Academy]
  +
** {{CathEncy|wstitle=Plato and Platonism}}
  +
* [http://platogeek.com Plato Bibliography at PlatoGeek]
  +
* [http://www.filozofie.eu/index.php?option=com_docman&Itemid=34 Online library "Vox Philosophiae"]
   
  +
{{Platonists}}
  +
  +
  +
  +
  +
  +
  +
<!--
  +
{{Link FA|fi}}
  +
  +
[[af:Plato]]
  +
[[als:Platon]]
 
[[ar:أفلاطون]]
 
[[ar:أفلاطون]]
[[bg:Платон]]
+
[[an:Platón]]
[[ba:Платон]]
+
[[ast:Platón]]
  +
[[az:Platon]]
 
[[bn:প্লেটো]]
 
[[bn:প্লেটো]]
  +
[[zh-min-nan:Platon]]
  +
[[ba:Платон]]
  +
[[be:Платон]]
  +
[[be-x-old:Платон]]
 
[[bs:Platon]]
 
[[bs:Platon]]
  +
[[br:Platon]]
  +
[[bg:Платон]]
 
[[ca:Plató]]
 
[[ca:Plató]]
  +
[[cv:Платон]]
 
[[cs:Platón]]
 
[[cs:Platón]]
[[cy:Plato]]
+
[[cy:Platon]]
 
[[da:Platon]]
 
[[da:Platon]]
 
[[de:Platon]]
 
[[de:Platon]]
 
[[et:Platon]]
 
[[et:Platon]]
 
[[el:Πλάτων]]
 
[[el:Πλάτων]]
  +
[[eml:Platån]]
 
[[es:Platón]]
 
[[es:Platón]]
 
[[eo:Platono]]
 
[[eo:Platono]]
  +
[[ext:Platón]]
 
[[eu:Platon]]
 
[[eu:Platon]]
 
[[fa:افلاطون]]
 
[[fa:افلاطون]]
  +
[[fo:Platon]]
 
[[fr:Platon]]
 
[[fr:Platon]]
  +
[[fy:Plato]]
 
[[ga:Platón]]
 
[[ga:Platón]]
  +
[[gd:Plato]]
[[gl:Platón - Πλάτων]]
 
  +
[[gl:Platón]]
  +
[[zh-classical:柏拉圖]]
 
[[ko:플라톤]]
 
[[ko:플라톤]]
  +
[[hy:Պլատոն]]
  +
[[hi:प्लेटो]]
 
[[hr:Platon]]
 
[[hr:Platon]]
 
[[io:Platon]]
 
[[io:Platon]]
 
[[ilo:Plato]]
 
[[ilo:Plato]]
  +
[[bpy:প্লেটো]]
 
[[id:Plato]]
 
[[id:Plato]]
 
[[is:Platon]]
 
[[is:Platon]]
Line 243: Line 472:
 
[[jv:Plato]]
 
[[jv:Plato]]
 
[[ka:პლატონი]]
 
[[ka:პლატონი]]
  +
[[sw:Plato]]
  +
[[ku:Platon]]
 
[[la:Plato]]
 
[[la:Plato]]
 
[[lv:Platons]]
 
[[lv:Platons]]
Line 248: Line 479:
 
[[hu:Platón]]
 
[[hu:Platón]]
 
[[mk:Платон]]
 
[[mk:Платон]]
  +
[[ml:പ്ലേറ്റോ]]
 
[[ms:Plato]]
 
[[ms:Plato]]
[[nl:Plato]]
+
[[cdo:Báik-lăk-dù]]
  +
[[my:ပလေးတိုး]]
[[nds:Platon]]
 
  +
[[nl:Plato (filosoof)]]
 
[[ja:プラトン]]
 
[[ja:プラトン]]
 
[[no:Platon]]
 
[[no:Platon]]
  +
[[nn:Platon]]
  +
[[oc:Platon]]
  +
[[uz:Aflotun]]
  +
[[ps:افلاطون]]
  +
[[pms:Platon]]
  +
[[nds:Platon]]
 
[[pl:Platon]]
 
[[pl:Platon]]
 
[[pt:Platão]]
 
[[pt:Platão]]
 
[[ro:Platon]]
 
[[ro:Platon]]
  +
[[qu:Platon]]
 
[[ru:Платон]]
 
[[ru:Платон]]
  +
[[sah:Былатыан]]
  +
[[sa:प्लातोन्]]
  +
[[sq:Platoni]]
  +
[[scn:Platuni]]
 
[[simple:Plato]]
 
[[simple:Plato]]
 
[[sk:Platón]]
 
[[sk:Platón]]
  +
[[cu:Пла́тѡнъ]]
 
[[sl:Platon]]
 
[[sl:Platon]]
 
[[sr:Платон]]
 
[[sr:Платон]]
  +
[[sh:Platon]]
 
[[fi:Platon]]
 
[[fi:Platon]]
 
[[sv:Platon]]
 
[[sv:Platon]]
  +
[[tl:Plato (pilosopo)]]
  +
[[ta:பிளேட்டோ]]
 
[[th:เพลโต]]
 
[[th:เพลโต]]
 
[[vi:Platon]]
 
[[vi:Platon]]
[[tr:Platon]]
+
[[tg:Афлотун]]
  +
[[tpi:Platon]]
  +
[[tr:Eflatun]]
 
[[uk:Платон]]
 
[[uk:Платон]]
  +
[[ur:افلاطون]]
  +
[[fiu-vro:Platon]]
  +
[[wa:Platon]]
  +
[[yi:פלאטו]]
  +
[[yo:Plato]]
  +
[[zh-yue:柏拉圖]]
  +
[[diq:Eflatun]]
  +
[[bat-smg:Platuons]]
 
[[zh:柏拉图]]
 
[[zh:柏拉图]]
  +
-->
 
 
{{enWP|Plato}}
 
{{enWP|Plato}}
  +
[[Category:Academic philosophers]]
  +
[[Category:Ancient Greek philosophers]]
  +
[[Category:Philosophers of language]]
  +
[[Category:Plato|*]]
  +
[[Category:Platonism|*]]
  +
[[Category:Political philosophers]]

Revision as of 22:55, 13 November 2012

Assessment | Biopsychology | Comparative | Cognitive | Developmental | Language | Individual differences | Personality | Philosophy | Social |
Methods | Statistics | Clinical | Educational | Industrial | Professional items | World psychology |

Philosophy Index: Aesthetics · Epistemology · Ethics · Logic · Metaphysics · Consciousness · Philosophy of Language · Philosophy of Mind · Philosophy of Science · Social and Political philosophy · Philosophies · Philosophers · List of lists


This article needs rewriting to enhance its relevance to psychologists..
Please help to improve this page yourself if you can..


Plato (Greek: Πλάτων, Plátōn, "broad")[1] (428/427 BC[a] – 348/347 BC), was a Classical Greek philosopher, mathematician, writer of philosophical dialogues, and founder of the Platonic Academy in Athens, the first institution of higher learning in the western world. Along with his mentor, Socrates, and his student, Aristotle, Plato helped to lay the foundations of Western philosophy.[2] Plato was originally a student of Socrates, and was as much influenced by his thinking as by what he saw as his teacher's unjust death.

Plato's sophistication as a writer is evident in his Socratic dialogues; thirty-five dialogues and thirteen letters have traditionally been ascribed to him, although modern scholarship doubts the authenticity of at least some of these.[3] Plato's writings have been published in several fashions; this has led to several conventions regarding the naming and referencing of Plato's texts.

Although there is little question that Plato lectured at the Academy that he founded, the pedagogical function of his dialogues, if any, is not known with certainty. The dialogues since Plato's time have been used to teach a range of subjects, mostly including philosophy, logic, rhetoric, mathematics, and other subjects about which he wrote.

Biography

Early life

Main article: Early life of Plato

Birth and family

Based on ancient sources, most modern scholars estimate that he was born in Athens or Aegina[b] between 429 and 423 BC[a] His father was Ariston. According to a disputed tradition, reported by Diogenes Laertius, Ariston traced his descent from the king of Athens, Codrus, and the king of Messenia, Melanthus.[4] Plato's mother was Perictione, whose family boasted of a relationship with the famous Athenian lawmaker and lyric poet Solon.[5] Perictione was sister of Charmides and niece of Critias, both prominent figures of the Thirty Tyrants, the brief oligarchic regime, which followed on the collapse of Athens at the end of the Peloponnesian War (404-403 BC).[6] Besides Plato himself, Ariston and Perictione had three other children; these were two sons, Adeimantus and Glaucon, and a daughter Potone, the mother of Speusippus (the nephew and successor of Plato as head of his philosophical Academy).[6] According to the Republic, Adeimantus and Glaucon were older than Plato.[7] Nevertheless, in his Memorabilia, Xenophon presents Glaucon as younger than Plato.[8]

Ariston tried to force his attentions on Perictione, but failed of his purpose; then the ancient Greek god Apollo appeared to him in a vision, and, as a result of it, Ariston left Perictione unmolested.[9] Another legend related that, while he was sleeping as an infant, bees had settled on the lips of Plato; an augury of the sweetness of style in which he would discourse philosophy.[10]

Ariston appears to have died in Plato's childhood, although the precise dating of his death is difficult.[11] Perictione then married Pyrilampes, her mother's brother,[12] who had served many times as an ambassador to the Persian court and was a friend of Pericles, the leader of the democratic faction in Athens.[13] Pyrilampes had a son from a previous marriage, Demus, who was famous for his beauty.[14] Perictione gave birth to Pyrilampes' second son, Antiphon, the half-brother of Plato, who appears in Parmenides.[15]

In contrast to his reticence about himself, Plato used to introduce his distinguished relatives into his dialogues, or to mention them with some precision: Charmides has one named after him; Critias speaks in both Charmides and Protagoras; Adeimantus and Glaucon take prominent parts in the Republic.[16] From these and other references one can reconstruct his family tree, and this suggests a considerable amount of family pride. According to Burnet, "the opening scene of the Charmides is a glorification of the whole [family] connection ... Plato's dialogues are not only a memorial to Socrates, but also the happier days of his own family".[17]

Name

According to Diogenes Laërtius, the philosopher was named Aristocles after his grandfather, but his wrestling coach, Ariston of Argos, dubbed him "Platon", meaning "broad," on account of his robust figure.[18] According to the sources mentioned by Diogenes (all dating from the Alexandrian period), Plato derived his name from the breadth (platytês) of his eloquence, or else because he was very wide (platýs) across the forehead.[19] In the 21st century some scholars disputed Diogenes, and argued that the legend about his name being Aristocles originated in the Hellenistic age.[c]

Education

Apuleius informs us that Speusippus praised Plato's quickness of mind and modesty as a boy, and the "first fruits of his youth infused with hard work and love of study".[20] Plato must have been instructed in grammar, music, and gymnastics by the most distinguished teachers of his time.[21] Dicaearchus went so far as to say that Plato wrestled at the Isthmian games.[22] Plato had also attended courses of philosophy; before meeting Socrates, he first became acquainted with Cratylus (a disciple of Heraclitus, a prominent pre-Socratic Greek philosopher) and the Heraclitean doctrines.[23]

Later life

Plato may have traveled in Italy, Sicily, Egypt and Cyrene.[24] Said to have returned to Athens at the age of forty, Plato founded one of the earliest known organized schools in Western Civilization on a plot of land in the Grove of Hecademus or Academus.[25] The Academy was "a large enclosure of ground which was once the property of a citizen at Athens named Academus... some, however, say that it received its name from an ancient hero",[26] and it operated until AD 529, when it was closed by Justinian I of Byzantium, who saw it as a threat to the propagation of Christianity. Many intellectuals were schooled in the Academy, the most prominent one being Aristotle.[27]

Plato and Socrates

File:Socrates and Plato.jpg

Plato and Socrates in a medieval picture.

Plato makes it clear, especially in his Apology of Socrates, that he was one of Socrates' devoted young followers. In that dialogue, Socrates is presented as mentioning Plato by name as one of those youths close enough to him to have been corrupted, if he were in fact guilty of corrupting the youth, and questioning why their fathers and brothers did not step forward to testify against him if he was indeed guilty of such a crime (33d-34a). Later, Plato is mentioned along with Crito, Critobolus, and Apollodorus as offering to pay a fine of 30 minas on Socrates' behalf, in lieu of the death penalty proposed by Meletus (38b). In the Phaedo, the title character lists those who were in attendance at the prison on Socrates' last day, explaining Plato's absence by saying, "Plato was ill" (Phaedo 59b).

The relationship between Plato and Socrates is problematic, however. Aristotle, for example, attributes a different doctrine with respect to the ideas to Plato and Socrates (Metaphysics 987b1–11), but Plato never speaks in his own voice in his dialogues. In the Second Letter, it says, "no writing of Plato exists or ever will exist, but those now said to be his are those of a Socrates become beautiful and new" (341c); if the Letter is Plato's, the final qualification seems to call into question the dialogues' historical fidelity. In any case, Xenophon and Aristophanes seem to present a somewhat different portrait of Socrates than Plato paints. Some have called attention to the problem of taking Plato's Socrates to be his mouthpiece, given Socrates' reputation for irony.[28]

The precise relationship between Plato and Socrates remains an area of contention among scholars.

Philosophy

Recurrent Themes

Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle

Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), a detail of The School of Athens, a fresco by Raphael. Aristotle gestures to the earth, representing his belief in knowledge through empirical observation and experience, while holding a copy of his Nicomachean Ethics in his hand. Plato holds his Timaeus and gestures to the heavens, representing his belief in The Forms.

For more details on this topic, see Aristotle's theory of universals.

Plato often discusses the father-son relationship and the "question" of whether a father's interest in his sons has much to do with how well his sons turn out. A boy in ancient Athens was socially located by his family identity, and Plato often refers to his characters in terms of their paternal and fraternal relationships. Socrates was not a family man, and saw himself as the son of his mother, who was apparently a midwife. A divine fatalist, Socrates mocks men who spent exorbitant fees on tutors and trainers for their sons, and repeatedly ventures the idea that good character is a gift from the gods. Crito reminds Socrates that orphans are at the mercy of chance, but Socrates is unconcerned. In the Theaetetus, he is found recruiting as a disciple a young man whose inheritance has been squandered. Socrates twice compares the relationship of the older man and his boy lover to the father-son relationship (Lysis 213a, Republic 3.403b), and in the Phaedo, Socrates' disciples, towards whom he displays more concern than his biological sons, say they will feel "fatherless" when he is gone. Many dialogues, like these, suggest that man-boy love (which is "spiritual") is a wise man's substitute for father-son biology (which is "bodily").

In several dialogues, Socrates floats the idea that Knowledge is a matter of recollection, and not of learning, observation, or study.[29] He maintains this view somewhat at his own expense, because in many dialogues, Socrates complains of his forgetfulness. Socrates is often found arguing that knowledge is not empirical, and that it comes from divine insight. He is quite consistent in believing in the immortality of the soul, and several dialogues end with long speeches imagining the afterlife. More than one dialogue contrasts knowledge and opinion, perception and reality, nature and custom, and body and soul. The only contrast to this is his Parmenides.

Several dialogues tackle questions about art: Socrates says that poetry is inspired by the muses, and is not rational. He speaks approvingly of this, and other forms of divine madness (drunkenness, eroticism, and dreaming) in the Phaedrus (265a–c), and yet in the Republic wants to outlaw Homer's great poetry, and laughter as well. In Ion, Socrates gives no hint of the disapproval of Homer that he expresses in the Republic. The dialogue Ion suggests that Homer's Iliad functioned in the ancient Greek world as the bible does today in the modern Christian world: as divinely inspired literature that can provide moral guidance, if only it can be properly interpreted.

On politics and art, religion and science, justice and medicine, virtue and vice, crime and punishment, pleasure and pain, rhetoric and rhapsody, human nature and sexuality, love and wisdom, Socrates and his company of disputants had something to say.

Metaphysics

Main article: Platonic realism

"Platonism" is a term coined by scholars to refer to the intellectual consequences of denying, as Socrates often does, the reality of the material world. In several dialogues, most notably the Republic, Socrates inverts the common man's intuition about what is knowable and what is real. While most people take the objects of their senses to be real if anything is, Socrates is contemptuous of people who think that something has to be graspable in the hands to be real. In the Theaetetus, he says such people are "eu a-mousoi", an expression that means literally, "happily without the muses" (Theaetetus 156a). In other words, such people live without the divine inspiration that gives him, and people like him, access to higher insights about reality.

Socrates's idea that reality is unavailable to those who use their senses is what puts him at odds with the common man, and with common sense. Socrates says that he who sees with his eyes is blind, and this idea is most famously captured in his allegory of the cave, and more explicitly in his description of the divided line. The allegory of the cave (begins Republic 7.514a) is a paradoxical analogy wherein Socrates argues that the invisible world is the most intelligible ("noeton") and that the visible world ("(h)oraton") is the least knowable, and the most obscure. (This is exactly the opposite of what Socrates says to Euthyphro in the soothsayer's namesake dialogue. There, Socrates tells Euthyphro that people can agree on matters of logic and science, and are divided on moral matters, which are not so easily verifiable.)

Socrates says in the Republic that people who take the sun-lit world of the senses to be good and real are living pitifully in a den of evil and ignorance. Socrates admits that few climb out of the den, or cave of ignorance, and those who do, not only have a terrible struggle to attain the heights, but when they go back down for a visit or to help other people up, they find themselves objects of scorn and ridicule.

According to Socrates, physical objects and physical events are "shadows" of their ideal or perfect forms, and exist only to the extent that they instantiate the perfect versions of themselves. Just as shadows are temporary, inconsequential epiphenomena produced by physical objects, physical objects are themselves fleeting phenomena caused by more substantial causes, the ideals of which they are mere instances. For example, Socrates thinks that perfect justice exists (although it is not clear where) and his own trial would be a cheap copy of it.

The allegory of the cave (often said by scholars to represent Plato's own epistemology and metaphysics) is intimately connected to his political ideology (often said to also be Plato's own), that only people who have climbed out of the cave and cast their eyes on a vision of goodness are fit to rule. Socrates claims that the enlightened men of society must be forced from their divine contemplations and compelled to run the city according to their lofty insights. Thus is born the idea of the "philosopher-king", the wise person who accepts the power thrust upon him by the people who are wise enough to choose a good master. This is the main thesis of Socrates in the Republic, that the most wisdom the masses can muster is the wise choice of a ruler.

The word metaphysics derives from the fact that Aristotle's musings about divine reality came after ("meta") his lecture notes on his treatise on nature ("physics"). The term is in fact applied to Aristotle's own teacher, and Plato's "metaphysics" is understood as Socrates' division of reality into the warring and irreconcilable domains of the material and the spiritual. The theory has been of incalculable influence in the history of Western philosophy and religion.

Theory of Forms

Main article: Theory of Forms

The Theory of Forms typically refers to Plato's belief that the material world as it seems to us is not the real world, but only a shadow of the real world. Plato spoke of forms in formulating his solution to the problem of universals. The forms, according to Plato, are roughly speaking archetypes or abstract representations of the many types and properties (that is, of universals) of things we see all around us.

Epistemology

Main article: Platonic epistemology

Many have interpreted Plato as stating that knowledge is justified true belief, an influential view which informed future developments in modern analytic epistemology. This interpretation is based on a reading of the Theaetetus wherein Plato argues that belief is to be distinguished from knowledge on account of justification. Many years later, Edmund Gettier famously demonstrated the problems of the justified true belief account of knowledge. This interpretation, however, imports modern analytic and empiricist categories onto Plato himself and is better read on its own terms than as Plato's view.

Really, in the Sophist, Statesman, Republic, and the Parmenides Plato himself associates knowledge with the apprehension of unchanging Forms and their relationships to one another (which he calls "expertise" in Dialectic). More explicitly, Plato himself argues in the Timaeus that knowledge is always proportionate to the realm from which it is gained. In other words, if one derives their account of something experientially, because the world of sense is in flux, the views therein attained will be mere opinions. And opinions are characterized by a lack of necessity and stability. On the other hand, if one derives their account of something by way of the non-sensible forms, because these forms are unchanging, so too is the account derived from them. It is only in this sense that Plato uses the term "knowledge."

In the Meno, Socrates uses a geometrical example to expound Plato's view that knowledge in this latter sense is acquired by recollection. Socrates elicits a fact concerning a geometrical construction from a slave boy, who could not have otherwise known the fact (due to the slave boy's lack of education). The knowledge must be present, Socrates concludes, in an eternal, non-experiential form.

The State

File:POxy3679 Parts Plato Republic.jpg

Papirus Oxyrhynchus, with fragment of Plato's Republic

Plato's philosophical views had many societal implications, especially on the idea of an ideal state or government. There is some discrepancy between his early and later views. Some of the most famous doctrines are contained in the Republic during his middle period, as well as in the Laws and the Statesman. However, because Plato wrote dialogues, it is assumed that Socrates is often speaking for Plato. This assumption may not be true in all cases.

Plato, through the words of Socrates, asserts that societies have a tripartite class structure corresponding to the appetite/spirit/reason structure of the individual soul. The appetite/spirit/reason stand for different parts of the body. The body parts symbolize the castes of society.[30]

  • Productive Which represents the abdomen.(Workers) — the labourers, carpenters, plumbers, masons, merchants, farmers, ranchers, etc. These correspond to the "appetite" part of the soul.
  • Protective Which represents the chest.(Warriors or Guardians) — those who are adventurous, strong and brave; in the armed forces. These correspond to the "spirit" part of the soul.
  • Governing Which represents the head. (Rulers or Philosopher Kings) — those who are intelligent, rational, self-controlled, in love with wisdom, well suited to make decisions for the community. These correspond to the "reason" part of the soul and are very few.

According to this model, the principles of Athenian democracy (as it existed in his day) are rejected as only a few are fit to rule. Instead of rhetoric and persuasion, Plato says reason and wisdom should govern. As Plato puts it:

"Until philosophers rule as kings or those who are now called kings and leading men genuinely and adequately philosophise, that is, until political power and philosophy entirely coincide, while the many natures who at present pursue either one exclusively are forcibly prevented from doing so, cities will have no rest from evils,... nor, I think, will the human race." (Republic 473c-d)
Plato i sin akademi, av Carl Johan Wahlbom (ur Svenska Familj-Journalen)

Plato in his academy, drawing after a painting by Swedish painter Carl Johan Wahlbom

Plato describes these "philosopher kings" as "those who love the sight of truth" (Republic 475c) and supports the idea with the analogy of a captain and his ship or a doctor and his medicine. Sailing and health are not things that everyone is qualified to practice by nature. A large part of the Republic then addresses how the educational system should be set up to produce these philosopher kings.

However, it must be taken into account that the ideal city outlined in the Republic is qualified by Socrates as the ideal luxurious city, examined to determine how it is that injustice and justice grow in a city (Republic 372e). According to Socrates, the "true" and "healthy" city is instead the one first outlined in book II of the Republic, 369c–372d, containing farmers, craftsmen, merchants, and wage-earners, but lacking the guardian class of philosopher-kings as well as delicacies such as "perfumed oils, incense, prostitutes, and pastries", in addition to paintings, gold, ivory, couches, a multitude of occupations such as poets and hunters, and war.

In addition, the ideal city is used as an image to illuminate the state of one's soul, or the will, reason, and desires combined in the human body. Socrates is attempting to make an image of a rightly ordered human, and then later goes on to describe the different kinds of humans that can be observed, from tyrants to lovers of money in various kinds of cities. The ideal city is not promoted, but only used to magnify the different kinds of individual humans and the state of their soul. However, the philosopher king image was used by many after Plato to justify their personal political beliefs. The philosophic soul according to Socrates has reason, will, and desires united in virtuous harmony. A philosopher has the moderate love for wisdom and the courage to act according to wisdom. Wisdom is knowledge about the Good or the right relations between all that exists.

Wherein it concerns states and rulers, Plato has made interesting arguments. For instance he asks which is better - a bad democracy or a country reigned by a tyrant. He argues that it is better to be ruled by a bad tyrant (since then there is only one person committing bad deeds) than be a bad democracy (since here all the people are now responsible for such actions.)

According to Plato, a state which is made up of different kinds of souls, will overall decline from an aristocracy (rule by the best) to a timocracy (rule by the honorable), then to an oligarchy (rule by the few), then to a democracy (rule by the people), and finally to tyranny (rule by one person, rule by a tyrant)[How to reference and link to summary or text].

Unwritten Doctrine

For a long time Plato's unwritten doctrine[31][32][33] had been considered unworthy of attention. Most of the books on Plato seem to diminish its importance. Nevertheless the first important witness who mentions its existence is Aristotle, who in his Physics (209 b) writes: "It is true, indeed, that the account he gives there [i.e. in Timaeus] of the participant is different from what he says in his so-called unwritten teaching (ἄγραφα δόγματα)." The term ἄγραφα δόγματα literally means unwritten doctrine and it stands for the most fundamental metaphysical teaching of Plato which he disclosed only to his most trusted fellows and kept secret from the public.

The reason for not revealing it to everyone is partially discussed in Phaedrus (276 c) where Plato criticizes the written transmission of knowledge as faulty, favoring instead the spoken logos: "he who has knowledge of the just and the good and beautiful ... will not, when in earnest, write them in ink, sowing them through a pen with words which cannot defend themselves by argument and cannot teach the truth effectually." The same argument is repeated in Plato's Seventh Letter (344 c): "every serious man in dealing with really serious subjects carefully avoids writing." In the same letter he writes (341 c): "I can certainly declare concerning all these writers who claim to know the subjects which I seriously study ... there does not exist, nor will there ever exist, any treatise of mine dealing therewith." Such secrecy is necessary in order not "to expose them to unseemly and degrading treatment" (344 d).

It is however said that Plato once disclosed this knowledge to the public in his lecture On the Good (Περὶ τἀγαθοῦ), in which the Good (τὸ ἀγαθόν) is identified with the One (the Unity, τὸ ἕν), the fundamental ontological principle. The content of this lecture has been transmitted by several witnesses, among others Aristoxenus who describes the event in the following words: "Each came expecting to learn something about the things which are generally considered good for men, such as wealth, good health, physical strength, and altogether a kind of wonderful happiness. But when the mathematical demonstrations came, including numbers, geometrical figures and astronomy, and finally the statement Good is One seemed to them, I imagine, utterly unexpected and strange; hence some belittled the matter, while others rejected it." Simplicius quotes Alexander of Aphrodisias who states that "according to Plato, the first principles of everything, including the Forms themselves are One and Indefinite Duality (ἡ ἀόριστος δυάς) which he called Large and Small (τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν) ... one might also learn this from Speusippus and Xenocrates and the others who were present at Plato's lecture on the Good"

Their account is in full agreement with Aristotle's description of Plato's metaphysical doctrine. In Metaphysics he writes: "Now since the Forms are the causes of everything else, he [i.e. Plato] supposed that their elements are the elements of all things. Accordingly the material principle is the Great and Small [i.e. the Dyad], and the essence is the One (τὸ ἕν), since the numbers are derived from the Great and Small by participation in the One" (987 b). "From this account it is clear that he only employed two causes: that of the essence, and the material cause; for the Forms are the cause of the essence in everything else, and the One is the cause of it in the Forms. He also tells us what the material substrate is of which the Forms are predicated in the case of sensible things, and the One in that of the Forms - that it is this the duality (the Dyad, ἡ δυάς), the Great and Small (τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν). Further, he assigned to these two elements respectively the causation of good and of evil" (988 a).

The most important aspect of this interpretation of Plato's metaphysics is the continuity between his teaching and the neoplatonic interpretation of Plotinus[34] or Ficino[35] which has been considered errorneous by many but may in fact have been directly influenced by oral transmission of Plato's doctrine. The first scholar who recognized the importance of the unwritten doctrine of Plato was Heinrich Gomperz who described it in his speech during the 7th International Congress of Philosophy in 1930.[36] All the sources related to the ἄγραφα δόγματα have been collected by Konrad Gaiser and published as Testimonia Platonica.[37] These sources have subsequently been interpreted by scholars from the german Tübingen School such as Hans Joachim Krämer or Thomas A. Szlezák.[38]

Works

File:Plato Republic 1713.jpg

Plato's The Republic, Latin edition cover, 1713

Thirty-five dialogues and thirteen letters have traditionally been ascribed to Plato, though modern scholarship doubts the authenticity of at least some of these. Plato's writings have been published in several fashions; this has led to several conventions regarding the naming and referencing of Plato's texts.

The usual system for making unique references to sections of the text by Plato derives from a 16th century edition of Plato's works by Henricus Stephanus. An overview of Plato's writings according to this system can be found in the Stephanus pagination article.

One tradition regarding the arrangement of Plato's texts is according to tetralogies. This scheme is ascribed by Diogenes Laertius to an ancient scholar and court astrologer to Tiberius named Thrasyllus.

In the list below, works by Plato are marked (1) if there is no consensus among scholars as to whether Plato is the author, and (2) if scholars generally agree that Plato is not the author of the work. Unmarked works are assumed to have been written by Plato.

  • I. Euthyphro, (The) Apology (of Socrates), Crito, Phaedo
  • II. Cratylus, Theaetetus, Sophist, Statesman
  • III. Parmenides, Philebus, (The) Symposium, Phaedrus
  • IV. First Alcibiades (1), Second Alcibiades (2), Hipparchus (2), (The) (Rival) Lovers (2)
  • V. Theages (2), Charmides, Laches, Lysis
  • VI. Euthydemus, Protagoras, Gorgias, Meno
  • VII. (Greater) Hippias (major) (1), (Lesser) Hippias (minor), Ion, Menexenus
  • VIII. Clitophon (1), (The) Republic, Timaeus, Critias
  • IX. Minos (2), (The) Laws, Epinomis (2), Epistles (1).

The remaining works were transmitted under Plato's name, most of them already considered spurious in antiquity, and so were not included by Thrasyllus in his tetralogical arrangement. These works are labelled as Notheuomenoi ("spurious") or Apocrypha.

  • Axiochus (2), Definitions (2), Demodocus (2), Epigrams, Eryxias (2), Halcyon (2), On Justice (2), On Virtue (2), Sisyphus (2).

Plato's Dialogues

The exact order in which Plato's dialogues were written is not known, nor is the extent to which some might have been later revised and rewritten.

Lewis Campbell was the first[39] to make exhaustive use of stylometry to prove objectively that the Critias, Timaeus, Laws, Philebus, Sophist, and Statesman were all clustered together as a group, while the Parmenides, Phaedrus, Republic, and Theaetetus belong to a separate group, which must be earlier (given Aristotle's statement in his Politics[40] that the Laws was written after the Republic; cf. Diogenes Laertius Lives 3.37). What is remarkable about Campbell's conclusions is that, in spite of all the stylometric studies that have been conducted since his time, perhaps the only chronological fact about Plato's works that can now be said to be proven by stylometry is the fact that Critias, Timaeus, Laws, Philebus, Sophist, and Statesman are the latest of Plato's dialogues, the others earlier.[41]

Increasingly in the most recent Plato scholarship, writers are skeptical of the notion that the order of Plato's writings can be established with any precision,[42] though Plato's works are still often characterized as falling at least roughly into three groups.[43] The following represents one such devision which is relatively common.[44] It should, however, be kept in mind that many of the positions in the ordering are still highly disputed, and also that the very notion that Plato's dialogues can or should be "ordered" is by no means universally accepted.

Early dialogues

Socrates figures in all of these, and they are considered the most faithful representations of the historical Socrates; hence they are also called the Socratic dialogues. Most of them consist of Socrates discussing a subject, often an ethical one (friendship, piety) with a friend or with someone presumed to be an expert on it. Through a series of questions he will show that apparently they do not understand it at all. It is left to the reader to figure out if "he" really understands "it". This makes these dialogues "indirect" teachings.

  • Apology
  • Charmides
  • Crito
  • Euthyphro
  • Ion
  • Laches
  • Lesser Hippias
  • Lysis
  • Menexenus
  • Protagoras is often considered one of the last of these "earlier" dialogues.

The following are often considered "transitional" or "pre-middle" dialogues:

  • Euthydemus
  • Gorgias
  • Meno

Middle dialogues

Late in the early dialogues Plato's Socrates actually begins supplying answers to some of the questions he asks, or putting forth positive doctrines. This is generally seen as the first appearance of Plato's own views. The first of these, that goodness is wisdom and that no one does evil willingly, was perhaps Socrates' own view. What becomes most prominent in the middle dialogues is the idea that knowledge comes of grasping unchanging forms or essences, paired with the attempts to investigate such essences. The immortality of the soul, and specific doctrines about justice, truth, and beauty, begin appearing here. The Symposium and the Republic are considered the centrepieces of Plato's middle period. The Parmenides and Theaetetus are often considered to come late in this period and transitional to the next, as they seem to treat the Theory of Forms critically (Parmenides) or not at all (Theaetetus).

  • Cratylus
  • Parmenides
  • Phaedo
  • Phaedrus
  • Republic
  • Symposium
  • Theaetetus

Late dialogues

File:Plato Timaeus.jpg

Early modern latin incunabulum of Plato's Timaeus, 1491

The Parmenides presents a series of criticisms of the theory of Forms which are widely taken to indicate Plato's abandonment of the doctrine. Some recent publications (e.g., Meinwald (1991)) have challenged this characterisation. In most of the remaining dialogues the theory is either absent or at least appears under a different guise in discussions about kinds or classes of things (the Timaeus may be an important, and hence controversially placed, exception). Socrates is either absent or a minor figure in the discussion. An apparently new method for doing dialectic known as "collection and division" is also featured, most notably in the Sophist and Statesman, explicitly for the first time in the Phaedrus, and possibly in the Philebus. A basic description of collection and division would go as follows: interlocutors attempt to discern the similarities and differences among things in order to get clear idea about what they in fact are. One understanding, suggested in some passages of the Sophist, is that this is what philosophy is always in the business of doing, and is doing even in the early dialogues.

The late dialogues are also an important place to look for Plato's mature thought on most of the issues dealt with in the earlier dialogues. There is much work still to be done by scholars on the working out of what these views are. The later works are agreed to be difficult and challenging pieces of philosophy. On the whole they are more sober and logical than earlier works, but may hold out the promise of steps towards a solution to problems which were systematically laid out in prior works.

  • Critias
  • Laws
  • Philebus
  • Sophist
  • Statesman
  • Timaeus

Narration of the dialogues

Plato never presents himself as a participant in any of the dialogues, and with the exception of the Apology, there is no suggestion that he heard any of the dialogues firsthand. Some dialogues have no narrator but have a pure "dramatic" form (examples: Meno, Gorgias, Phaedrus, Crito, Euthyphro), some dialogues are narrated by Socrates, wherein he speaks in first person (examples: Lysis, Charmides, Republic). One dialogue, Protagoras, begins in dramatic form but quickly proceeds to Socrates' narration of a conversation he had previously with the sophist for whom the dialogue is named; this narration continues uninterrupted till the dialogue's end.

File:Anselm Feuerbach 003.jpg

Plato's Symposium (Anselm Feuerbach, 1873)

The three dialogues, Phaedo, Symposium, and Theaetetus, also begin in dramatic form but then proceed to virtually uninterrupted narration by followers of Socrates, and all, apparently, based on their distant memory or secondhand reports. Phaedo, an account of Socrates' final conversation and hemlock drinking, is narrated by Phaedo to Echecrates in a foreign city many years after the execution took place. The Symposium is narrated by Apollodorus, a Socratic disciple, apparently to Glaucon. Apollodorus assures his listener that he is recounting the story, which took place when he himself was an infant, not from his own memory, but as remembered by Aristodemus, who told him the story years ago. In the beginning of the Theaetetus (142c-143b), Euclides says that he compiled the conversation from notes he took based on what Socrates told him of his conversation with the title character. The rest of the Theaetetus is presented as a "book" written in dramatic form and read by one of Euclides' slaves (143c). Some scholars take this as an indication that Plato had by this date wearied of the narrated form.[45] With the exception of the Theaetetus, Plato gives no explicit indication as to how these orally transmitted conversations came to be written down. Other dialogues, such as the Phaedo, Symposium, and Parmenides, do suggest that such conversations were faithfully recalled and transmitted by Socrates' followers.[46]

Trial of Socrates

See main article: Trial of Socrates

The trial of Socrates is the central, unifying event of the great Platonic dialogues. Because of this, Plato's Apology is perhaps the most often read of the dialogues. In the Apology, Socrates tries to dismiss rumors that he is a sophist and defends himself against charges of disbelief in the gods and corruption of the young. Socrates insists that long-standing slander will be the real cause of his demise, and says the legal charges are essentially false. Socrates famously denies being wise, and explains how his life as a philosopher was launched by the Oracle at Delphi. He says that his quest to resolve the riddle of the oracle put him at odds with his fellow man, and that this is the reason he has been mistaken for a menace to the city-state of Athens.

Unity and Diversity of the Dialogues

If Plato's important dialogues do not refer to Socrates' execution explicitly, they allude to it, or use characters or themes that play a part in it. Five dialogues foreshadow the trial: In the Theaetetus (210d) and the Euthyphro (2a–b) Socrates tells people that he is about to face corruption charges. In the Meno (94e–95a), one of the men who brings legal charges against Socrates, Anytus, warns him about the trouble he may get into if he does not stop criticizing important people. In the Gorgias, Socrates says that his trial will be like a doctor prosecuted by a cook who asks a jury of children to choose between the doctor's bitter medicine and the cook's tasty treats (521e–522a). In the Republic (7.517e), Socrates explains why an enlightened man (presumably himself) will stumble in a courtroom situation. The Apology is Socrates' defense speech, and the Crito and Phaedo take place in prison after the conviction. In the Protagoras, Socrates is a guest at the home of Callias, son of Hipponicus, a man whom Socrates disparages in the Apology as having wasted a great amount of money on sophists' fees.

Two other important dialogues, the Symposium and the Phaedrus, are linked to the main storyline by characters. In the Apology (19b, c), Socrates says Aristophanes slandered him in a comic play, and blames him for causing his bad reputation, and ultimately, his death. In the Symposium, the two of them are drinking together with other friends. The character Phaedrus is linked to the main story line by character (Phaedrus is also a participant in the Symposium and the Protagoras) and by theme (the philosopher as divine emissary, etc.) The Protagoras is also strongly linked to the Symposium by characters: all of the formal speakers at the Symposium (with the exception of Aristophanes) are present at the home of Callias in that dialogue. Charmides and his guardian Critias are present for the discussion in the Protagoras. Examples of characters crossing between dialogues can be further multiplied. The Protagoras contains the largest gathering of Socratic associates.

In the dialogues for which Plato is most celebrated and admired, Socrates is concerned with human and political virtue, has a distinctive personality, and friends and enemies who "travel" with him from dialogue to dialogue. This is not to say that Socrates is consistent: a man who is his friend in one dialogue may be an adversary or subject of his mockery in another. For example, Socrates praises the wisdom of Euthyphro many times in the Cratylus, but makes him look like a fool in the Euthyphro. He disparages sophists generally, and Prodicus specifically in the Apology, yet tells Theaetetus in his namesake dialogue that he admires Prodicus and has directed many pupils to him. In Cratylus (384b-c), Socrates says that he studied with Cratylus, and took his one-drachma course because he could not afford the full fifty-drachma course. Socrates' ideas are also not consistent within or between or among dialogues.

Platonic Scholarship

File:0042MC.jpg

"The safest general characterisation of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato." (Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality, 1929).

Plato's thought is often compared with that of his most famous student, Aristotle, whose reputation during the Western Middle Ages so completely eclipsed that of Plato that the Scholastic philosophers referred to Aristotle as "the Philosopher". However, in the Byzantine Empire, the study of Plato continued.

The Medieval scholastic philosophers did not have access to the works of Plato, nor the knowledge of Greek needed to read them. Plato's original writings were essentially lost to Western civilization until they were brought from Constantinople in the century before its fall, by George Gemistos Plethon.[How to reference and link to summary or text] Medieval scholars knew of Plato only through translations into Latin from the translations into Arabic by Persian and Arab scholars. These scholars not only translated the texts of the ancients, but expanded them by writing extensive commentaries and interpretations on Plato's and Aristotle's works (see Al-Farabi, Avicenna, Averroes).

Only in the Renaissance, with the general resurgence of interest in classical civilization, did knowledge of Plato's philosophy become widespread again in the West. Many of the greatest early modern scientists and artists who broke with Scholasticism and fostered the flowering of the Renaissance, with the support of the Plato-inspired Lorenzo de Medici, saw Plato's philosophy as the basis for progress in the arts and sciences. By the 19th century, Plato's reputation was restored, and at least on par with Aristotle's.

Notable Western philosophers have continued to draw upon Plato's work since that time. Plato's influence has been especially strong in mathematics and the sciences. He helped to distinguish between pure and applied mathematics by widening the gap between "arithmetic", now called Number Theory and "logistic", now called arithmetic. He regarded logistic as appropriate for business men and men of war who "must learn the art of numbers or he will not know how to array his troops," while arithmetic was appropriate for philosophers "because he has to arise out of the sea of change and lay hold of true being."[47] Plato's resurgence further inspired some of the greatest advances in logic since Aristotle, primarily through Gottlob Frege and his followers Kurt Gödel, Alonzo Church, and Alfred Tarski; the last of these summarised his approach by reversing Aristotle's famous declaration of sedition from the Nicomachean Ethics (1096a15: Amicus Plato sed magis amica veritas - "Plato is a friend, but truth is a greater friend") to Inimicus Plato sed magis inimica falsitas ("Plato is an enemy, but falsehood is a greater enemy"). Albert Einstein drew on Plato's understanding of an immutable reality that underlies the flux of appearances for his objections to the probabilistic picture of the physical universe propounded by Niels Bohr in his interpretation of quantum mechanics.[How to reference and link to summary or text] Conversely, thinkers that diverged from ontological models and moral ideals in their own philosophy, have tended to disparage Platonism from more or less informed perspectives. Thus Friedrich Nietzsche attacked Plato's moral and political theories, Martin Heidegger argued against Plato's alleged obfuscation of Being, and Karl Popper argued in The Open Society and Its Enemies (1945) that Plato's alleged proposal for a government system in the Republic was prototypically totalitarian. Leo Strauss is considered by some as the prime thinker involved in the recovery of Platonic thought in its more political, and less metaphysical, form. Deeply influenced by Nietzsche and Heidegger, Strauss nonetheless rejects their condemnation of Plato and looks to the dialogues for a solution to what all three thinkers acknowledge as 'the crisis of the West.'

Academic Genealogy
Notable teachers Notable students
Socrates Amyclus of Heraclea

Aristonymus
Aristotle
Axiothea of Phlius
Callippus of Athens
Coriscus of Scepsis
Demetrius of Amphipolis
Dion of Syracuse
Erastus of Scepsis
Euaeon of Lampsacus
Eudoxus of Cnidus
Heraclides of Aenus
Heraclides of Pontus
Hermias of Atarneus
Hestiaeus of Perinthus
Hippothales of Athens
Lastheneia of Mantinea
Philippus of Opus
Phormio
Python of Aenus
Speusippus of Athens
Timolaus of Cyzicus
Theophrastus
Xenocrates of Chalcedon


See also

  • Alexander Nehamas
  • Cambridge Platonists
  • Eric A. Havelock
  • Jacob Klein (philosopher)
  • Platonic love
  • Platonic Realism
  • Mitchell Miller
  • Seth Benardete
  • Seventh Letter (Plato)

Notes

a. ^  The grammarian Apollodorus argues in his Chronicles that Plato was born in the first year of the eighty-eighth Olympiad (427 BC), on the seventh day of the month Thargelion; according to this tradition the god Apollo was born this day.[48] According to another biographer of him, Neanthes, Plato was eighty-four years of age at his death.[48] If we accept Neanthes' version, Plato was younger than Isocrates by six years, and therefore he was born in the second year of the 87th Olympiad, the year Pericles died (429 BC).[49] According to the Suda, Plato was born in Aegina in the 88th Olympiad amid the preliminaries of the Peloponnesian war, and he lived 82 years.[50] Sir Thomas Browne also believes that Plato was born in the 88th Olympiad.[51] Renaissance Platonists celebrated Plato's birth on November 7.[52] Wilamowitz-Moellendorff estimates that Plato was born when Diotimos was archon eponymous, namely between July 29 428 BC and July 24 427 BC.[53] Greek philologist Ioannis Kalitsounakis believes that the philosopher was born on May 26 or 27 427 BC, while Jonathan Barnes regards 428 BC as year of Plato's birth.[54] For her part, Debra Nails asserts that the philosopher was born in 424/423 BC.[52]

b. ^  Diogenes Laertius mentions that Plato "was born, according to some writers, in Aegina in the house of Phidiades the son of Thales". Diogenes mentions as one of his sources the Universal History of Favorinus. According to Favorinus, Ariston, Plato's family, and his family were sent by Athens to settle as cleruchs (colonists retaining their Athenian citizenship), on the island of Aegina, from which they were expelled by the Spartans after Plato's birth there.[55] Nails points out, however, that there is no record of any Spartan expulsion of Athenians from Aegina between 431-411 BC.[56] On the other hand, at the Peace of Nicias, Aegina was silently left under Athens' control, and it was not until the summer of 411 that the Spartans overran the island.[57] Therefore, Nails concludes that "perhaps Ariston was a cleruch, perhaps he went to Aegina in 431, and perhaps Plato was born on Aegina, but none of this enables a precise dating of Ariston's death (or Plato's birth).[56] Aegina is regarded as Plato's place of birth by Suda as well.[50]

c. ^  Plato was a common name, of which 31 instances are known at Athens alone.[58]

Notes

  1. Diogenes Laertius 3.4; p. 21, David Sedley, Plato's Cratylus, Cambridge University Press 2003
  2. "Plato". Encyclopaedia Britannica. (2002). 
  3. For example, some were excluded from Thrasyllus' tetralogies. See e.g. the table of contents to John M. Cooper (ed.), Plato: Complete Works, Hackett, 1997.
  4. Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, III
    * D. Nails, "Ariston", 53
    * U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Plato, 46
  5. Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, I
  6. 6.0 6.1 W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy', IV, 10
    * A.E. Taylor, Plato, xiv
    * U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Plato, 47
  7. Plato, Republic, 2.368a
    * U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Plato, 47
  8. Xenophon, Memorabilia, 3.6.1
  9. Apuleius, De Dogmate Platonis, 1
    * Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, I
    "Plato". Suda. 
  10. Cicero, De Divinatione, I, 36
  11. D. Nails, "Ariston", 53
    * A.E. Taylor, Plato, xiv
  12. Plato, Charmides, 158a
    * D. Nails, "Perictione", 53
  13. Plato, Charmides, 158a
    * Plutarch, Pericles, IV
  14. Plato, Gorgias, 481d and 513b
    * Aristophanes, Wasps, 97
  15. Plato, Parmenides, 126c
  16. W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy, IV, 11
  17. C.H. Kahn, Plato and the Socratic Dialogue, 186
  18. Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, IV
  19. Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, IV
    * A. Notopoulos, The Name of Plato, 135
  20. Apuleius, De Dogmate Platonis, 2
  21. Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, IV
    * W. Smith, Plato, 393
  22. Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, V
  23. Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1.987a
  24. McEvoy, James (1984). Plato and The Wisdom of Egypt. Irish Philosophical Journal 1 (2).
  25. Huntington Cairns, Introduction to Plato: The Collected Dialogues, p. xiii.
  26. Robinson, Arch. Graec. I i 16.
  27. Biography of Aristotle. ClassicNote. GradeSaver LLC. URL accessed on 2007-12-03.
  28. Leo Strauss, The City and Man (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964), 50–1.
  29. Baird, Forrest E.; Walter Kaufmann (2008). From Plato to Derrida, Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Pearson Prentice Hall.
  30. Gaarder, Jostein (1996). Sophie's World, 91, New York City: Berkley.
  31. Rodriguez- Grandjean, Pablo. Philosophy and Dialogue: Plato's Unwritten Doctrines from a Hermeneutical Point of View, Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, in Boston, Massachusetts from August 10-15, 1998.
  32. Reale, Giovanni, and Catan, John R., A History of Ancient Philosophy, SUNY Press, 1990. ISBN 0791405168. Cf. p.14 and onwards.
  33. Krämer, Hans Joachim, and Catan, John R., Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics: A Work on the Theory of the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines of Plato with a Collection of the Fundamental Documents, (Translated by John R. Catan), SUNY Press, 1990. ISBN 0791404331, Cf. pp.38-47
  34. Plotinus describes this in the last part of his final Ennead (VI, 9) entitled On the Good, or the One (Περὶ τἀγαθοῦ ἢ τοῦ ἑνός). Jens Halfwassen states in Der Aufstieg zum Einen (2006) that "Plotinus' ontology - which should rather be called Plotinus' henology - is a rather accurate philosophical renewal and continuation of Plato's unwritten doctrine, i.e. the doctrine rediscovered by Krämer and Gaiser."
  35. In one of his letters (Epistolae 1612) Ficino writes: "The main goal of the divine Plato ... is to show one principle of things which he called the One (τὸ ἕν)", cf. Marsilio Ficino, Briefe des Mediceerkreises, Berlin, 1926, p. 147.
  36. H. Gomperz, Plato's System of Philosophy, in: G. Ryle (ed.), Proceedings of the Seventh International Congress of Philosophy, London 1931, pp. 426-431. Reprinted in: H. Gomperz, Philosophical Studies, Boston, 1953, pp. 119-24.
  37. K. Gaiser, Testimonia Platonica. Le antiche testimonianze sulle dottrine non scritte di Platone, Milan, 1998. First published as Testimonia Platonica. Quellentexte zur Schule und mündlichen Lehre Platons as an appendix to Gaiser's Platons Ungeschriebene Lehre, Stuttgart, 1963.
  38. For a bried description of the problem see for example K. Gaiser, Plato's enigmatic lecture "On the Good", Phronesis 25 (1980), pp. 5-37. A detailed analysis is given by Krämer in his Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics: A Work on the Theory of the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines of Plato With a Collection of the Fundamental Documents, Albany: SUNY Press, 1990. Another good description is by Giovanni Reale: Toward a New Interpretation of Plato, Washington, D.C.: CUA Press, 1997. Reale summarizes the results of his research in A History of Ancient Philosophy: Plato and Aristotle, Albany: SUNY Press, 1990. However the most complete analysis of the consequences of such an approach is given by Thomas A. Szlezak in his fundamental Reading Plato, New York: Routledge, 1999. Another supporter of this interpretation is the german philosopher Karl Albert, cf. Griechische Religion und platonische Philosophie, Hamburg, 1980 or Einführung in die philosophische Mystik, Darmstadt, 1996. Hans-Georg Gadamer is also sympathetic towards it, cf. J. Grondin, Gadamer and the Tübingen School and Gadamer's 1968 article Plato's Unwritten Dialectic reprinted in his Dialogue and Dialectic. Gadamer's final position on the subject is stated in his introduction to La nuova interpretazione di Platone. Un dialogo tra Hans-Georg Gadamer e la scuola di Tubinga, Milano 1998.
  39. p. 9, John Burnet, Platonism, University of California Press 1928.
  40. 1264b24-27
  41. p. xiv, J. Cooper (ed.), Plato: Complete Works, Hackett 1997.
  42. Richard Kraut, "Plato", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, accessed 24 June 2008; Malcolm Schofield (1998, 2002), "Plato", in E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/A088, accessed 24 June 2008; Christopher Rowe, "Interpreting Plato", in H. Benson (ed.), A Companion to Plato, Blackwell 2006.
  43. T. Brickhouse & N. Smith, "Plato", The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, accessed 24 June 2008.
  44. See W. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy, vol. 4, Cambridge University Press 1975; G. Vlastos, Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher, Cambridge University Press 1991; T. Penner, "Socrates and the Early Dialogues", in R. Kraut (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato, Cambridge University Press 1992; C. Kahn, Plato and the Socratic Dialogue, Cambridge University Press 1996; G. Fine, Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the Soul, Oxford University Press 1999.
  45. sect. 177, J. Burnet, Greek Philosophy, MacMillan 1950.
  46. pp. 23-24, W. K. C. Guthrie, Socrates, Cambridge 1971.
  47. Boyer, Carl B. (1991). "The age of Plato and Aristotle" A History of Mathematics, Second Edition, 86, John Wiley & Sons, Inc.. "Plato is important in the history of mathematics largely for his role as inspirer and director of others, and perhaps to him is due the sharp distinction in ancient Greece between arithmetic (in the sense of the theory of numbers) and logistic (the technique of computation). Plato regarded logistic as appropriate for the businessman and for the man of war, who "must learn the art of numbers or he will not know how to array his troops." The philosopher, on the other hand, must be an arithmetician "because he has to arise out of the sea of change and lay hold of true being.""
  48. 48.0 48.1 Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, II
  49. F.W. Nietzsche, Werke, 32
  50. 50.0 50.1 "Plato". Suda. 
  51. T. Browne, Pseudodoxia Epidemica, XII
  52. 52.0 52.1 D. Nails, The Life of Plato of Athens, 1
  53. U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Plato, 46
  54. "Plato". Encyclopaedia Britannica. (2002). 
    * "Plato". Encyclopaedic Dictionary The Helios Volume V (in Greek). (1952). 
  55. Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, III
  56. 56.0 56.1 D. Nails, "Ariston", 54
  57. Thucydides, 5.18
    * Thucydides, 8.92
  58. W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy, IV, 10
    * L. Tarán, Plato's Alleged Epitaph, 61

References

Primary sources (Greek and Roman)

Secondary sources

  • Browne, Sir Thomas (1646-1672). Pseudodoxia Epidemica.
  • Guthrie, W.K.C. (1986). A History of Greek Philosophy: Volume 4, Plato: The Man and His Dialogues: Earlier Period, Cambridge University Press.
  • Kahn, Charles H. (2004). "The Framework" Plato and the socratic dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form, Cambridge University Press.
  • Nails, Debra (2006). "The Life of Plato of Athens" A Companion to Plato edited by Hugh H. Benson, Blackwell Publishing.
  • Nails, Debra (2002). "Ariston/Perictione" The People of Plato: A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics, Hackett Publishing.
  • Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm (1967). "Vorlesungsaufzeichnungen" Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe (in German), Walter de Gruyter.
  • Notopoulos, A. (April 1939). The Name of Plato. Classical Philology 34 (No.2): 135–145.
  • "Plato". Encyclopaedia Britannica. (2002). 
  • "Plato". Encyclopaedic Dictionary The Helios Volume XVI (in Greek). (1952). 
  • "Plato". Suda. (10th century). 
  • Smith, William (1870). "Plato" Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology.
  • Tarán, Leonardo (2001). Collected Papers 1962-1999, Brill Academic Publishers.
  • Taylor, Alfred Edward (2001). Plato: The Man and his Work, Courier Dover Publications.
  • Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Ulrich von (2005 (first edition 1917)). Plato: his Life and Work (translated in Greek by Xenophon Armyros, Kaktos.

Further reading

  • Allen, R.E. (2006). Studies in Plato's Metaphysics II. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-18-6
  • Ambuel, David (2006). Image and Paradigm in Plato's Sophist. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-004-9
  • Bakalis, Nikolaos (2005). Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments, Trafford Publishing ISBN 1-4120-4843-5
  • Barrow, Robin (2007). Plato: Continuum Library of Educational Thought, Continuum.
  • Cadame, Claude (1999). Indigenous and Modern Prespectives on Tribal Initiation Rites: Education According to Plato, pp. 278-312, in Padilla, Mark William (editor), "Rites of Passage in Ancient Greece: Literature, Religion, Society", Bucknell University Press, 1999. ISBN 0-8387-5418-X
  • Cooper, John M. & Hutchinson, D. S. (Eds.) (1997). Plato: Complete Works, Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.
  • Corlett, J. Angelo (2005). Interpreting Plato's Dialogues. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-02-5
  • Durant, Will (1926). The Story of Philosophy, Simon & Schuster.
  • Derrida, Jacques (1972). La dissémination, Paris: Seuil. (esp. cap.: La Pharmacie de Platon, 69-199) ISBN 2-02-001958-2
  • Field, G.C. (Guy Cromwell) (1969). The Philosophy of Plato, 2nd ed. with an appendix by R. C. Cross., London: Oxford University Press.
  • Fine, Gail (2000). Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology Oxford University Press, USA, ISBN 0-19-875206-7
  • Garvey, James (2006,). Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books, Continuum.
  • Guthrie, W. K. C. (1986). A History of Greek Philosophy (Plato - The Man & His Dialogues - Earlier Period), Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-31101-2
  • Guthrie, W. K. C. (1986). A History of Greek Philosophy (Later Plato & the Academy) Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-31102-0
  • Havelock, Eric (2005). Preface to Plato (History of the Greek Mind), Belknap Press, ISBN 0-674-69906-8
  • Hamilton, Edith & Cairns, Huntington (Eds.) (1961). The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Including the Letters, Princeton Univ. Press.
  • Irwin, Terence (1995). Plato's Ethics, Oxford University Press, USA, ISBN 0-19-508645-7
  • Jackson, Roy (2001). Plato: A Beginner's Guide, London: Hoder & Stroughton.
  • Kochin, Michael S. (2002). Gender and Rhetoric in Plato’s Political Thought, Cambridge Univ. Press.
  • Kraut, Richard (Ed.) (1993). The Cambridge Companion to Plato, Cambridge University Press.
  • Krämer, Hans Joachim (1990). Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics, SUNY Press.
  • Lilar, Suzanne (1954), Journal de l'analogiste, Paris, Éditions Julliard; Reedited 1979, Paris, Grasset. Foreword by Julien Gracq
  • Lilar, Suzanne (1963), Le couple, Paris, Grasset. Translated as Aspects of Love in Western Society in 1965, with a foreword by Jonathan Griffin London, Thames and Hudson.
  • Lilar, Suzanne (1967) A propos de Sartre et de l'amour , Paris, Grasset.
  • Lundberg, Phillip (2005). Tallyho - The Hunt for Virtue: Beauty,Truth and Goodness Nine Dialogues by Plato: Pheadrus, Lysis, Protagoras, Charmides, Parmenides, Gorgias, Theaetetus, Meno & Sophist, Authorhouse.
  • Melchert, Norman (2002). The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy, McGraw Hill.
  • Meinwald, Constance Chu (1991). Plato's Parmenides, Oxford University Press.
  • Miller, Mitchell (2004). The Philosopher in Plato's Statesman. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-16-2
  • Mohr, Richard D. (2006). God and Forms in Plato - and other Essays in Plato's Metaphysics. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-01-8
  • Moore, Edward (2007). Plato. Philosophy Insights Series. Tirril, Humanities-Ebooks. ISBN 978-1-84760-047-9
  • Nightingale, Andrea Wilson. (1995). "Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy", Cambridge University Press. ISBN 052148264X
  • Reale, Giovanni (1990). A History of Ancient Philosophy: Plato and Aristotle, SUNY Press.
  • Reale, Giovanni (1997). Toward a New Interpretation of Plato, CUA Press.
  • Sallis, John (1996). Being and Logos: Reading the Platonic Dialogues, Indiana University Press.
  • Sallis, John (1999). Chorology: On Beginning in Plato's "Timaeus", Indiana University Press.
  • Sayre, Kenneth M. (2006). Plato's Late Ontology: A Riddle Resolved. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-09-4
  • Seung, T. K. (1996). Plato Rediscovered: Human Value and Social Order. Rowman and Littlefield. ISBN: 0847681122
  • Szlezak, Thomas A. (1999). Reading Plato, Routledge.
  • Taylor, A. E. (2001). Plato: The Man and His Work, Dover Publications, ISBN 0-486-41605-4
  • Vlastos, Gregory (1981). Platonic Studies, Princeton University Press, ISBN 0-691-10021-7
  • Vlastos, Gregory (2006). Plato's Universe - with a new Introducution by Luc Brisson, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-13-1
  • Oxford University Press publishes scholarly editions of Plato's Greek texts in the Oxford Classical Texts series, and some translations in the Clarendon Plato Series.
  • Harvard University Press publishes the hardbound series Loeb Classical Library, containing Plato's works in Greek, with English translations on facing pages.
  • Thomas Taylor has translated Plato's complete works.
  • Smith, William. (1867 — original). Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology, University of Michigan/Online version.
  • Aspects of antiquity: Discoveries and Controversies by M.I. Finley, issued 1969 by The Viking Press, Inc.
  • Interpreting Plato: The Dialogues as Drama by James A. Arieti, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc. ISBN 0-8476-7662-5

External links

Wikisource
English Wikisource has original text related to this article:
Plato
Wikisource
Greek Wikisource has original text related to this article:
Platon
Wikiquote-logo-en
Wikiquote has a collection of quotations related to:
Commons logo
Wikimedia Commons has media related to:
- Greek & English hyperlinked text

Template:Platonists




This page uses Creative Commons Licensed content from Wikipedia (view authors).