Wikia

Psychology Wiki

Changes: Adaptationism

Edit

Back to page

(update wp)
 
Line 1: Line 1:
 
{{BioPsy}}
 
{{BioPsy}}
   
'''Adaptationism''' is a set of methods in the evolutionary sciences for distinguishing the products of [[adaptation (biology)|adaptation]] from [[Trait (biological)|trait]]s that arise through other processes. It is employed in fields such as [[ethology]] and [[evolutionary psychology]] that are concerned with identifying adaptations. [[George C. Williams|George Williams]]' ''[[Adaptation and Natural Selection]]'' was highly influential in its development, defining some of the heuristics, such as complex functional design, used to identify adaptations.
+
'''Adaptationism''' is a set of methods in the evolutionary sciences for distinguishing the products of [[adaptation (biology)|adaptation]] from [[Trait (biological)|trait]]s that arise through other processes. It is employed in fields such as [[ethology]] and [[evolutionary psychology]] that are concerned with identifying adaptations. [[George C. Williams|George Williams]]' ''[[Adaptation and Natural Selection]]'' was highly influential in its development, defining some of the heuristics, such as complex functional design, used to identify adaptations.
   
==Criticism==
+
==Debate==
   
Adaptationism is sometimes characterized by critics as an unsubstantiated assumption that all or most traits are [[Optimization (mathematics)|optimal]] adaptations. Critics (most notably [[Richard Lewontin]] and [[Stephen Jay Gould]]) contend that the adaptationsists ([[John Maynard Smith]], [[W.D. Hamilton]] and [[Richard Dawkins]] being frequent examples) have over-emphasized the power of [[natural selection]] to have shape individual traits to an [[evolution|evolutionary]] optimum, and ignored the role of developmental constraints, and other factors to explain extant morphological and behavioural traits.
+
Adaptationism is sometimes characterized by critics as an unsubstantiated assumption that all or most traits are [[Optimization (mathematics)|optimal]] adaptations. Critics (most notably [[Richard Lewontin]] and [[Stephen Jay Gould]]) contend that the adaptationists ([[John Maynard Smith]], [[W.D. Hamilton]] and [[Richard Dawkins]] being frequent examples) have over-emphasized the power of [[natural selection]] to shape individual traits to an [[evolution]]ary optimum, and ignored the role of developmental constraints, and other factors to explain extant morphological and behavioural traits.
   
Adaptationists are accused by their critics of using [[ad-hoc]] "Just So Stories" to make their theories unfalsifiable. The critics, in turn, have often been accused of attacking [[Straw man|straw men]], rather than the actual views of supposed adaptationists.
+
Adaptationism could also be characterized as an approach to studying evolution of form and function that attempts to frame the existence and persistence of traits on the scenario that each of them arose independently due to how that trait improved the reproductive success of the organism's ancestors. Adaptationism is also a description of "folk biology" where non-experts see that, in general, organisms have an amazing array of adaptations, then apply this principle too broadly and describe everything as adaptive.
   
Adaptationist researchers respond by asserting that they, too, follow [[George C. Williams|George Williams]]' depiction of adaptation as an "onerous concept" that should only be applied in light of strong evidence. This evidence can be generally characterized as the successful prediction of novel phenomena based on the hypothesis that design details of adaptations should fit a complex evolved design to respond to a specific set of selection pressures. In evolutionary psychology, researchers such as [[David Buss]] contend that the bulk of research findings that were uniquely predicted through adaptationist hypothesizing comprise evidence of the methods' validity.
+
==Criteria of calling something adaptive==
   
The debate has occasionally been colored by a political subtext, with the [[Marxist]]-leaning Lewontin and Gould accusing sociobiologists of employing adaptationist fallacies in supporting socially regressive views of biological determinism. The history of this debate, and others related to it, are covered in detail by Cronin (1992) and Segerstråle (2000). Adaptationists such as [[Steven Pinker]] have also suggested that the debate has a strong [[ad hominem]] component. Some suggest that the controversy over the relative importance of various factors would be a quiet debate over subtleties if the critics were less prone to caricaturing their opponents{{Fact|date=February 2007}}.
+
If and only if a trait fulfills the following criteria will evolutionary biologists in general declare the trait an adaptation:
   
==References==
+
# The trait is a variation of an earlier form.
* Cronin, H. (1992). ''The Ant and the Peacock: Altruism and Sexual Selection from Darwin to Today''. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
+
# The trait is heritable through the transmission of genes.
* [[Stephen Jay Gould|Gould, S.J.]] & [[Richard Lewontin|Lewontin, R.C.]] (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. ''Proceedings of the Royal Society London B.'' 205: 581—598.
+
# The trait enhances reproductive success.
* [[Richard Lewontin|Lewontin, R.C.]] 1979. Sociobiology as an adaptationist program. ''Behavioral Science'' 24: 5—14.
+
* [[Richard Lewontin|Lewontin, R.C.]] 1991. ''Biology as Ideology: The Doctrine of DNA.'' New York: Harper Collins
+
Adaptationists too agree with these rules, but their opponents maintain adaptationists are sometimes too eager to take an imaginative leap where the evidence is spotty or ambiguous.
* [[John Maynard Smith|Maynard Smith, J.]] (1988). ''Did Darwin get it right? Essays on games, sex and evolution'' London:Penguin books. ISBN 0-14-023013-0.
+
* Orzack, S.H. & Sober, E.R., eds. (2001). ''Adaptationism and Optimality''. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
+
Evolution cannot form perfect organisms for numerous reasons. Foremost is that some elements of an organism's physiology are subject to constraints that environmental pressure cannot alter.
* Segerstråle, U. 2000. ''Defenders of the Truth: The Battle for Science in the Sociobiology Debate and Beyond''. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
+
* Sober, E. (1998) ''Six Sayings about Adaptationism'' in D. Hull and M. Ruse (eds) ''The Philosophy of Biology'' Oxford: Oxford University Press.
+
==Anatomical Constraints==
  +
  +
Anatomical constraints are features of organism's [[anatomy]] that are prevented from change by being ''constrained'' in some way. When organisms diverge from a common ancestor and inherit certain characteristics which become modified by natural selection of mutant phenotypes, it is as if some are traits are locked in place and are unable to change in certain ways. Some textbook [[anatomical constraints]] often include examples of structures that connect parts of the body together though a physical link.
  +
  +
These links are hard if not impossible to break because evolution usually requires that anatomy be formed by small consecutive modifications in populations through generations. Dr. [[Randolf Nesse]], in his book: ''Why We Get sick'' explains that the [[Blind spot (vision)|"blind spot"]] in the vertebrate eye caused by the nerve fibers running in front of the [[retina]] and blocking vision in parts. He says that [[natural selection]] has come up with an elaborate work-around of the eyes wobbling back-and-forth to correct for this, but vertebrates have not found the solution embodied in [[cephalopod]] eyes, where the optic nerve does not obstruct the view. He goes on to say that a likely reason for this is that in order for the nerve to migrate over evolutionary time it would have to be disconnected or "cut" at some point to complete the trip. This disconnection would not allow for the message to go from the eye to the brain and this would render those mutant individuals blind, so making the transition virtually impossible. See also: [[Evolution of the eye]].
  +
  +
Other examples often cited for the same reason are the [[cranial nerves]] in [[tetrapods]]. Some of the best derived models of early vertebrate evolution have been sharks, skates, and rays (collectively [[chondrichthyes]]). In chondrichthyes the cranial nerves run from the part of the brain that interprets sensory information, and radiate out towards the organs that produce those sensations. In tetrapods however, and [[mammals]] in particular, the [[nerves]] take an elaborate winding path through the [[cranium]]. They go up down and around structures that evolved after the common ancestor with sharks. This is because when their locations shifted over time each stage had to remain connected. See also: [[Cranial nerves]].
  +
  +
It is not possible to have a number of generations of organisms that are blind (as in the vertebrate eye example) or generations with areas that are not [[nervous system|"innervated"]], nor is it possible that in transition the [[vas deferens|"spermatochord"]] becomes severed, then continue to migrate to reach around the pelvis. These would not work because the intermediates with severed connections would be poorly suited for their environments and would fail to reproduce. So these links are maintained throughout millions of years simply because departure from the status quo is inviable.
  +
  +
==Genetic Constraints==
  +
  +
Genetic constraints provide another force that inhibits the effectiveness of natural selection. Examples include [[pleiotropy]], [[epistasis]], and [[polygenic traits]].
  +
  +
With [[pleiotropy]] a hypothetical gene would be selected by natural selection or other related mechanisms. The trait would be selected for its effects on reproductive success. This is well established as how traits evolve. However, some genes control multiple traits. Selection that influences [[epistasis]] is a case where the regulation or expression of one gene, depends on one or several others. This is true for a good number of genes though to differing extents. The reason why this leads to muddied responses is that selection for a trait that is epistatically based can mean that an [[allele]] for a gene that is epistatic when selected would happen to affect others. This leads to the [[coregulation]] of others for a reason other than there is an adaptive quality to each of those traits. Like with pleiotropy, traits could reach fixation in a population as a by-product of selection for another.
  +
  +
In the context of development the difference between pleiotropy and epistasis is not so clear but at the genetic level the distinction is more clear. With these traits as being by-products of others it can ultimately be said that these traits evolved by not that they necessarily represent adaptations.
  +
  +
[[Polygenic]] traits are traits that are controlled by a number of different genes. Counter to what is commonly taught in high school and introductory biology classes with beginner's [[Mendelian Genetics]], traits are rarely controlled by one single discrete, either/or allele. Things like human height vary with a great range because this trait is controlled by several different genes.
  +
  +
To drastically change some quantitative trait controlled by many genes, this could require mutations in more than one gene or changes in regulation of more than one gene. This means that mutations effect these systems more on a one-at-a-time basis. Because of this
  +
  +
Adaptationists are accused by their critics of using ''[[Ad hoc|ad-hoc]]'' [[Just-so story|"just-so stories"]] to make their theories unfalsifiable. The critics, in turn, have often been accused of attacking [[Straw man|straw men]], rather than the actual views of supposed adaptationists.
  +
  +
==Adaptationist rebuttals==
  +
  +
Adaptationist researchers respond by asserting that they, too, follow [[George C. Williams|George Williams]]' depiction of adaptation as an "onerous concept" that should only be applied in light of strong evidence. This evidence can be generally characterized as the successful prediction of novel phenomena based on the hypothesis that design details of adaptations should fit a complex evolved design to respond to a specific set of selection pressures. In evolutionary psychology, researchers such as [[David Buss]] contend that the bulk of research findings that were uniquely predicted through adaptationist hypothesizing comprise evidence of the methods' validity.
  +
  +
Adaptationists such as [[Steven Pinker]] have also suggested that the debate has a strong [[ad hominem]] component. Some suggest that the controversy over the relative importance of various factors would be a quiet debate over subtleties if the critics were less prone to caricaturing their opponents{{Citation needed|date=February 2007}}.
   
 
==See also==
 
==See also==
  +
{{Portal|Evolutionary biology}}
 
* [[Adaptation]]
 
* [[Adaptation]]
 
* [[Gene-centered view of evolution]]
 
* [[Gene-centered view of evolution]]
 
* [[Spandrel (biology)|Spandrel]]
 
* [[Spandrel (biology)|Spandrel]]
  +
* [[Beneficial acclimation hypothesis]]
  +
  +
==References==
  +
<references/>
  +
* {{cite book|last=Cronin|first=H.|coauthors=|authorlink=|title=The Ant and the Peacock: Altruism and Sexual Selection from Darwin to Today|edition=|publisher=Cambridge University Press|location=Cambridge|year=1992|isbn=0-521-32937-X|series=}}
  +
* {{cite journal|last=Gould|first=S.J.|coauthors=[[Richard Lewontin|Lewontin, R.C.]]|authorlink=Stephen Jay Gould|title=The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme|year=1979|journal=Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B|volume=205|issue=1161|pages=581–598|doi=10.1098/rspb.1979.0086|pmid=42062}}
  +
* {{cite journal|last=Lewontin|first=R.C.|authorlink=Richard Lewontin|year=1979|title=Sociobiology as an adaptationist program|url=|journal=Behavioral Science|volume=24|issue=1|pages=5–14|doi=10.1002/bs.3830240103|pmid=435219}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Lewontin|first=R.C.|coauthors=|authorlink=Richard Lewontin|title=Biology as Ideology: The Doctrine of DNA|edition=|publisher=Harper Collins|location=New York|year=1993|isbn=0-06-097519-9|series=}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Maynard Smith|first=J.|coauthors=|authorlink=John Maynard Smith|title=Did Darwin get it right? Essays on games, sex and evolution|edition=|publisher=Penguin books|location=London|year=1988|isbn=0-14-023013-0|series=}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Orzack|first=S.H.|coauthors=& Sober, E.R., eds.|authorlink=|title=Adaptationism and Optimality|edition=|publisher=Cambridge University Press|location=Cambridge|year=2001|isbn=0-521-59166-X|series=}}
  +
* {{cite book|last=Sober|first=E.|chapter=Six Sayings about Adaptationism|title=The Philosophy of Biology|editor=D. Hull and M. Ruse (eds)|edition=|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=Oxford|year=1998|isbn=0-19-875213-x|series=}}
   
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
*[https://notes.utk.edu/bio/greenberg.nsf/0/fc9136a487aaad9585256cff00663c2e?OpenDocument information from "Deep Ethology"] course website, by Neil Greenberg
+
*[https://notes.utk.edu/bio/greenberg.nsf/0/fc9136a487aaad9585256cff00663c2e?OpenDocument Information from "Deep Ethology"] course website, by Neil Greenberg
 
*[http://cogweb.ucla.edu/Debate/CEP_Gould.html Tooby & Cosmides comments on Maynard Smith's New York Review of Books piece on Gould et al.]
 
*[http://cogweb.ucla.edu/Debate/CEP_Gould.html Tooby & Cosmides comments on Maynard Smith's New York Review of Books piece on Gould et al.]
   
[[Category:evolutionary biology]]
+
[[Category:Evolution]]
   
  +
<!--
  +
[[ca:Adaptacionisme]]
 
[[es:Adaptacionismo]]
 
[[es:Adaptacionismo]]
  +
[[pl:Adaptacjonizm]]
  +
[[pt:Adaptacionismo]]
  +
-->
 
{{enWP|Adaptationism}}
 
{{enWP|Adaptationism}}

Latest revision as of 23:54, November 8, 2011

Assessment | Biopsychology | Comparative | Cognitive | Developmental | Language | Individual differences | Personality | Philosophy | Social |
Methods | Statistics | Clinical | Educational | Industrial | Professional items | World psychology |

Biological: Behavioural genetics · Evolutionary psychology · Neuroanatomy · Neurochemistry · Neuroendocrinology · Neuroscience · Psychoneuroimmunology · Physiological Psychology · Psychopharmacology (Index, Outline)


Adaptationism is a set of methods in the evolutionary sciences for distinguishing the products of adaptation from traits that arise through other processes. It is employed in fields such as ethology and evolutionary psychology that are concerned with identifying adaptations. George Williams' Adaptation and Natural Selection was highly influential in its development, defining some of the heuristics, such as complex functional design, used to identify adaptations.

DebateEdit

Adaptationism is sometimes characterized by critics as an unsubstantiated assumption that all or most traits are optimal adaptations. Critics (most notably Richard Lewontin and Stephen Jay Gould) contend that the adaptationists (John Maynard Smith, W.D. Hamilton and Richard Dawkins being frequent examples) have over-emphasized the power of natural selection to shape individual traits to an evolutionary optimum, and ignored the role of developmental constraints, and other factors to explain extant morphological and behavioural traits.

Adaptationism could also be characterized as an approach to studying evolution of form and function that attempts to frame the existence and persistence of traits on the scenario that each of them arose independently due to how that trait improved the reproductive success of the organism's ancestors. Adaptationism is also a description of "folk biology" where non-experts see that, in general, organisms have an amazing array of adaptations, then apply this principle too broadly and describe everything as adaptive.

Criteria of calling something adaptiveEdit

If and only if a trait fulfills the following criteria will evolutionary biologists in general declare the trait an adaptation:

  1. The trait is a variation of an earlier form.
  2. The trait is heritable through the transmission of genes.
  3. The trait enhances reproductive success.

Adaptationists too agree with these rules, but their opponents maintain adaptationists are sometimes too eager to take an imaginative leap where the evidence is spotty or ambiguous.

Evolution cannot form perfect organisms for numerous reasons. Foremost is that some elements of an organism's physiology are subject to constraints that environmental pressure cannot alter.

Anatomical ConstraintsEdit

Anatomical constraints are features of organism's anatomy that are prevented from change by being constrained in some way. When organisms diverge from a common ancestor and inherit certain characteristics which become modified by natural selection of mutant phenotypes, it is as if some are traits are locked in place and are unable to change in certain ways. Some textbook anatomical constraints often include examples of structures that connect parts of the body together though a physical link.

These links are hard if not impossible to break because evolution usually requires that anatomy be formed by small consecutive modifications in populations through generations. Dr. Randolf Nesse, in his book: Why We Get sick explains that the "blind spot" in the vertebrate eye caused by the nerve fibers running in front of the retina and blocking vision in parts. He says that natural selection has come up with an elaborate work-around of the eyes wobbling back-and-forth to correct for this, but vertebrates have not found the solution embodied in cephalopod eyes, where the optic nerve does not obstruct the view. He goes on to say that a likely reason for this is that in order for the nerve to migrate over evolutionary time it would have to be disconnected or "cut" at some point to complete the trip. This disconnection would not allow for the message to go from the eye to the brain and this would render those mutant individuals blind, so making the transition virtually impossible. See also: Evolution of the eye.

Other examples often cited for the same reason are the cranial nerves in tetrapods. Some of the best derived models of early vertebrate evolution have been sharks, skates, and rays (collectively chondrichthyes). In chondrichthyes the cranial nerves run from the part of the brain that interprets sensory information, and radiate out towards the organs that produce those sensations. In tetrapods however, and mammals in particular, the nerves take an elaborate winding path through the cranium. They go up down and around structures that evolved after the common ancestor with sharks. This is because when their locations shifted over time each stage had to remain connected. See also: Cranial nerves.

It is not possible to have a number of generations of organisms that are blind (as in the vertebrate eye example) or generations with areas that are not "innervated", nor is it possible that in transition the "spermatochord" becomes severed, then continue to migrate to reach around the pelvis. These would not work because the intermediates with severed connections would be poorly suited for their environments and would fail to reproduce. So these links are maintained throughout millions of years simply because departure from the status quo is inviable.

Genetic ConstraintsEdit

Genetic constraints provide another force that inhibits the effectiveness of natural selection. Examples include pleiotropy, epistasis, and polygenic traits.

With pleiotropy a hypothetical gene would be selected by natural selection or other related mechanisms. The trait would be selected for its effects on reproductive success. This is well established as how traits evolve. However, some genes control multiple traits. Selection that influences epistasis is a case where the regulation or expression of one gene, depends on one or several others. This is true for a good number of genes though to differing extents. The reason why this leads to muddied responses is that selection for a trait that is epistatically based can mean that an allele for a gene that is epistatic when selected would happen to affect others. This leads to the coregulation of others for a reason other than there is an adaptive quality to each of those traits. Like with pleiotropy, traits could reach fixation in a population as a by-product of selection for another.

In the context of development the difference between pleiotropy and epistasis is not so clear but at the genetic level the distinction is more clear. With these traits as being by-products of others it can ultimately be said that these traits evolved by not that they necessarily represent adaptations.

Polygenic traits are traits that are controlled by a number of different genes. Counter to what is commonly taught in high school and introductory biology classes with beginner's Mendelian Genetics, traits are rarely controlled by one single discrete, either/or allele. Things like human height vary with a great range because this trait is controlled by several different genes.

To drastically change some quantitative trait controlled by many genes, this could require mutations in more than one gene or changes in regulation of more than one gene. This means that mutations effect these systems more on a one-at-a-time basis. Because of this

Adaptationists are accused by their critics of using ad-hoc "just-so stories" to make their theories unfalsifiable. The critics, in turn, have often been accused of attacking straw men, rather than the actual views of supposed adaptationists.

Adaptationist rebuttalsEdit

Adaptationist researchers respond by asserting that they, too, follow George Williams' depiction of adaptation as an "onerous concept" that should only be applied in light of strong evidence. This evidence can be generally characterized as the successful prediction of novel phenomena based on the hypothesis that design details of adaptations should fit a complex evolved design to respond to a specific set of selection pressures. In evolutionary psychology, researchers such as David Buss contend that the bulk of research findings that were uniquely predicted through adaptationist hypothesizing comprise evidence of the methods' validity.

Adaptationists such as Steven Pinker have also suggested that the debate has a strong ad hominem component. Some suggest that the controversy over the relative importance of various factors would be a quiet debate over subtleties if the critics were less prone to caricaturing their opponents[citation needed].

See alsoEdit

.

ReferencesEdit

  • Cronin, H. (1992). The Ant and the Peacock: Altruism and Sexual Selection from Darwin to Today, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Gould, S.J., Lewontin, R.C. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B 205 (1161): 581–598.
  • Lewontin, R.C. (1979). Sociobiology as an adaptationist program. Behavioral Science 24 (1): 5–14.
  • Lewontin, R.C. (1993). Biology as Ideology: The Doctrine of DNA, New York: Harper Collins.
  • Maynard Smith, J. (1988). Did Darwin get it right? Essays on games, sex and evolution, London: Penguin books.
  • Orzack, S.H.; & Sober, E.R., eds. (2001). Adaptationism and Optimality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sober, E. (1998). "Six Sayings about Adaptationism" D. Hull and M. Ruse (eds) The Philosophy of Biology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

External linksEdit

This page uses Creative Commons Licensed content from Wikipedia (view authors).

Around Wikia's network

Random Wiki